Skip to main content
Top
Gepubliceerd in: Psychological Research 5/2012

Open Access 01-09-2012 | Original Article

Harleß’ Apparatus of Will: 150 years later

Auteurs: Roland Pfister, Markus Janczyk

Gepubliceerd in: Psychological Research | Uitgave 5/2012

share
DELEN

Deel dit onderdeel of sectie (kopieer de link)

  • Optie A:
    Klik op de rechtermuisknop op de link en selecteer de optie “linkadres kopiëren”
  • Optie B:
    Deel de link per e-mail
insite
ZOEKEN

Abstract

As the empirical study of action control via ideomotor effect anticipations continues to uncover more and more aspects of this fundamental process, it is time to look back to the 19th century roots of the theory to assess which classical ideas are supported by contemporary research. In turn, classic ideas might stimulate studies on aspects of the ideomotor mechanism that have not yet been addressed empirically. The present article is a tribute to this classical work—more precisely to the article “Der Apparat des Willens” [The Apparatus of Will], published by Emil Harleß 150 years ago. At a closer look, Harleß does not only present a concise description of the ideomotor mechanism; he also presents a wealth of intriguing ideas that deserve empirical investigation.
Opmerkingen

Electronic supplementary material

The online version of this article (doi:10.​1007/​s00426-011-0362-3) contains supplementary material, which is available to authorized users.

Early ideomotor theory

Over the last two decades, ideomotor theory as a 19th century philosophical approach to human action has stimulated numerous intriguing experiments on this fundamental mechanism (for recent reviews see Nattkemper, Ziessler, & Frensch, 2010; Shin, Proctor, & Capaldi, 2010). While these experiments steadily increased our understanding of the ideomotor mechanism, classical comprehensive accounts of ideomotor action control are about to fall into oblivion. Symptomatically, of the several hundred papers on ideomotor theory published to date, only one targeted earlier formulations of the theory (Stock & Stock, 2004).1
Among these earlier formulations are several comprehensive accounts for ideomotor theory, starting with Herbart’s (1825) Psychologie als Wissenschaft neu gegründet auf Erfahrung, Metaphysik und Mathematik, and continuing with Lotze’s (1852) Medicinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele and Harleß’ (1861) Der Apparat des Willens. These classical works offer a wealth of intriguing ideas and point towards important questions that contemporary research has not answered yet. Still, they are not as well known as would be expected based on their potential merit for contemporary research. At least two factors are responsible for this circumstance: First, most classical treatises clearly differ from contemporary research papers in that their length exceeds the concise format of the latter ones where relevant information is assumed to be more readily extractable from a minimum of pages. The second factor is obvious from the titles cited above: most comprehensive 19th century accounts of ideomotor theory were written in German language and are thus inaccessible to the majority of contemporary researchers. The present article aims at making the most concise of these classical accounts (Harleß, 1861) available to the English-speaking world. To this end, the following sections first provide a few biographical notes on the author and continue with a summary of the key points in his Der Apparat des Willens.

Emil Harleß’ and the “physiological-psychological mechanism”

In contrast to his philosophical predecessors Herbart and Lotze, Emil Harleß (Fig. 1) was a physiologist, who had studied medicine, physics, and chemistry in Würzburg and Berlin (Meyers Konversationslexikon 1885-1892). During the first years of his academic career at the University of Erlangen, he focused on experiments on general anaesthetic drugs and published a seminal report in this area together with Ernst von Bibra (Bibra & Harleß, 1847).
Only after becoming a full professor at the University of Munich (Martin, 1857) he started to investigate the “physiological-psychological mechanism”, what would today be subsumed under the terms physiological psychology or cognitive neuroscience (e.g., Harleß, 1862). One year before his death—exactly 150 years ago—he published an article where he discussed ideomotor theory in the broader framework of the mind–body problem. This article—Der Apparat des Willens [The Apparatus of Will]—is arguably the most concise and comprehensive account for ideomotor action formulated prior to James’s (1890/1981) Principles of Psychology (cf. Hommel, 2003; Stock & Stock, 2004). It contains a wealth of innovative ideas, some of which have already received empirical support and others that are just now being addressed by experimental studies. An English translation of the Apparatus of Will is available as supplementary online material whereas the following sections highlight its most important ideas for contemporary research.2

The Apparatus of Will and future directions

Contemporary accounts of ideomotor theory concentrate on the immediate role of sensory anticipations for the production of motor actions (Hoffmann, 1993, 2003; Hommel, 2009; Hommel, Müsseler, Aschersleben, & Prinz, 2001; Kunde, 2001, 2003). To the contrary, Harleß (1861) conceives ideomotor theory as a broader approach to the philosophical mind–body problem, including the classical controversy about human free will and related issues such as its legal implications. Consequently, the first part of the article (“The foundations of voluntary action”) contains a thorough discussion of the relationship of voluntariness, consciousness, and purposefulness of voluntary actions.
Regarding this distinction, Harleß (1861) arrives at the interesting conclusion that an action is most likely to appear voluntary to an observer if it does not serve an apparent purpose, i.e., when it does not seem to be motivated by situational demands (labelled incidental actions). The conclusion that such incidental actions give rise to the most intense impression of voluntariness is supported by several recent studies on imitation behaviour. In these studies, human infants and chimpanzees tended to imitate unusual object-oriented actions, such as pressing a button with one’s forehead, only if the agent could have used his hands easily instead of the forehead but not if the agent’s hands were occupied (e.g., Buttelmann, Carpenter, Call, & Tomasello, 2007; Gergely, Bekkering, & Király, 2002). In accordance with Harleß’ deduction, actions that do not seem to be motivated by situational demands (in this case: having his hands free instead of carrying an object), do indeed seem to have a special influence on the observer. The discussion of such incidental actions also leads to a fine-grained analysis of voluntary action. For instance, Harleß suggested that voluntary actions do comprise decisions about whether an action should be carried out at all—a notion that was recently taken up in the What-When-Whether model of intentional action (Brass & Haggard, 2008).
The first part of the article ends with the claim that incidental actions are the key to understanding voluntary actions in general. This idea was addressed in various recent studies where the term ‘incidental actions’ was substituted by the concepts of self-initiated (Jahanshahi et al., 1995), endogenous (Astor-Jack & Haggard, 2005), and intention-based actions (Herwig, Prinz, & Waszak, 2007; Pfister, Kiesel, & Melcher, 2010). The question of how such actions—in contrast to immediate reactions to external stimuli—might promote ideomotor learning or the anticipation of distal action effects is just now being addressed by empirical studies (Dutzi & Hommel, 2009; Haering & Kiesel, (2011); Herwig et al., 2007; Herwig & Waszak, 2009; Janczyk, Pfister, & Kunde, (2011); Pfister et al., 2010; Pfister, Kiesel, & Hoffmann, 2011; Stock & Hoffmann, 2002; Wolfensteller & Ruge, (2011)).
The second part of the article (“The physiology of incidental actions”) is concerned with the physiological implementation of voluntary actions in general and incidental actions in particular. Like other physiologists of his time (e.g., Laycock, 1845), Harleß (1861) assumes two qualitatively different functional units of the nervous system: a sensory unit (sensorium) and a motor unit (motorium). Accordingly, activations have to be relayed from the former system to the latter system in order to produce adaptive action. A considerable proportion of the article is devoted to this question which has had a relatively limited impact on contemporary research. Notable exceptions include recent neuroimaging studies on the acquisition of bidirectional action-effect associations (Elsner et al., 2002; Melcher, Weidema, Eenshuistra, Hommel, & Gruber, 2008), the sensory nature of effect anticipations (Kühn, Seurinck, Fias, & Waszak, 2010; Kühn, Keizer, Rombouts, & Hommel, 2011), and the electrophysiological signature of effect anticipations (Waszak & Herwig, 2007; Nikolaev, Ziessler, van Leeuwen, & Dimova, 2008). In this respect, Harleß seems to have foreseen the advent of neuroimaging methods in claiming that “activity of the soul” will inevitably increase the blood flow in the activated brain regions—preparing the theoretical stage for an fMRI analysis of ideomotor processes. Still, however, the neurophysiological mechanisms that relay effect anticipations to motor centres are virtually unknown and will have to be uncovered in the years to come. A promising start in this enterprise might be the integration of ideomotor theory and recent concepts in computational neuroscience, such as forward and inverse models (e.g., Wolpert & Kawato, 1998).
A third part of Harleß’ (1861) article covers the acquisition of bidirectional action-effect representations for humans and animals (“The acquisition of behavioural competence”). Like prior accounts (Lotze, 1852), this description is relatively vague; yet, it suggests an important role of incidental movements during prenatal development. This discussion already contains important thoughts about the contextual nature of action-effect representations that were later addressed empirically (Hoffmann & Sebald, 2000; Kiesel & Hoffmann, 2004). The later ontogenetic development of action-effect representations is not covered in the Apparatus of Will but is certainly an important addition to the considerations raised by Harleß (e.g., Eenshuistra, Weidema, & Hommel, 2004; Karbach, Kray, & Hommel, 2011; Verschoor, Weidema, Biro, & Hommel, 2010). Interestingly, Harleß explicitly suggested the acquisition of action-effect representations to be subjected to preparedness for learning specific action-effect relations while other relations are much harder to acquire. Even though this notion was empirically tested in operant conditioning experiments with rodents (Bolles, 1970; Randolph, 1986) it has not yet been applied to human agents.3
The major part of Harleß’ (1861) article describes a physiologically motivated schematic of action control via ideomotor effect anticipations (“A physiological-psychological mechanism for voluntary actions”; Fig. 2). Interestingly, Harleß already employed the modern term of action effects and pointed towards the contextual dependence of action-effect associations (Hoffmann, 1993; Hoffmann & Sebald, 2000). In contrast to contemporary experiments which exclusively studied the situational context, Harleß proposed a much broader definition, including the internal context such as the current mood or arousal level. Whereas the internal context has been investigated in other domains of psychology (e.g., regarding mood-congruent memory; Bower, 1981), its role for ideomotor processes still has to be uncovered. Furthermore, Harleß explicitly discusses the role of proximal and different types of distal effects—a discussion that empirical studies are just now beginning to take up (Janczyk, Skirde, Weigelt, & Kunde, 2009). Importantly, Harleß also emphasises a unique role of the valence of actions and their effects for acquisition and application of action-effect associations that, up to now, has only played a minor role for contemporary research and theory (but see Beckers, De Houwer, & Eelen, 2002; Eder, Müsseler, & Hommel, (2011); Kunde, Lozo, & Neumann, (2011)). Both, the distinction between proximal and distal feedback and the role of valenced action effects, have direct implications for future research. Action effects are no longer to be seen as a homogenous class of events that are only defined by their contingent mapping to an action. To the contrary, the exact properties of action effects have to be taken into account to arrive at a clearer understanding of their role for human and non-human action control.

Conclusions

The preceding sections aimed at exemplifying how Harleß’ (1861) conception of the Apparatus of Will might guide future research on ideomotor action control. Two further points, however, should not be forgotten. The first point is concerned with theoretical underpinnings of ideomotor action control. Since Harleß’ days, major theoretical advances were sparse and centred about the learning mechanisms of Anticipatory Behavioural Control (Hoffmann, 1993, 2003) and the immediate interface of perception and action as conceptualised in the Theory of Event Coding (Hommel et al., 2001; see also Hommel, 2004, 2009). Still, ideomotor theory has remained a relatively vague idea—a metatheoretical framework to integrate empirical findings with limited capabilities for deriving predictions for a specific experimental setting. Future theoretical developments are needed to overcome this status: Which circumstances promote the anticipation of distal action effects? What is the role of emotional states in ideomotor processing? Is it possible to derive a computational framework for ideomotor theory?
These questions point at important theoretical developments in order to integrate the available evidence. Yet, such an enterprise can only be effective if the insights from ideomotor research and theory can be effectively disseminated to those outside the immediate scientific community. In the words of Emil Harleß (1861, p. 73): “May the appeal of this secret, which everybody carries within him- or herself, help to attract attention to this isolated chapter of physiological psychology […] also from a much broader point of view.”

Acknowledgements

We thank B. Hommel, S. Jordan, W. Kunde, and R. Proctor for their helpful comments on an earlier version of this manuscript.
Open Access This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Noncommercial License ( https://​creativecommons.​org/​licenses/​by-nc/​2.​0 ), which permits any noncommercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author(s) and source are credited.
share
DELEN

Deel dit onderdeel of sectie (kopieer de link)

  • Optie A:
    Klik op de rechtermuisknop op de link en selecteer de optie “linkadres kopiëren”
  • Optie B:
    Deel de link per e-mail

Onze productaanbevelingen

BSL Psychologie Totaal

Met BSL Psychologie Totaal blijf je als professional steeds op de hoogte van de nieuwste ontwikkelingen binnen jouw vak. Met het online abonnement heb je toegang tot een groot aantal boeken, protocollen, vaktijdschriften en e-learnings op het gebied van psychologie en psychiatrie. Zo kun je op je gemak en wanneer het jou het beste uitkomt verdiepen in jouw vakgebied.

BSL Academy Accare GGZ collective

Bijlagen

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.
Voetnoten
1
In addition to this paper, two historical articles sketch the life of Thomas Laycock (Leff, 1991, 2003), a key figure of the British Tradition of ideomotor theory (cf. Stock & Stock, 2004).
 
2
Translating a 19th century German article into modern English is difficult for a number of reasons. Most importantly, a translation that is close to the original wording will effectively obscure its gist in most instances because of the completely different approach to scientific writing that is obvious from many classical treatises. For this reason, we focused on the meaning of the text at the expense of a limited conservation of its original style. Following the same line of argument, we introduced subheadings as a major stylistic change to make the text more accessible.
 
3
In contrast to the study of preparedness, there is another striking imbalance regarding the explicit study of ideomotor action-effect associations which was almost exclusively studied with human participants. A notable exception is a study on action-effect associations in the fruit fly Drosophila (Gerber & Hendel, 2006).
 
Literatuur
go back to reference Astor-Jack, T., & Haggard, P. (2005). Intention and reactivity. In G. W. Humphreys & J. M. Riddoch (Eds.), Attention in action: Advances from cognitive neuroscience (pp. 109–130). Hove: Psychology Press.CrossRef Astor-Jack, T., & Haggard, P. (2005). Intention and reactivity. In G. W. Humphreys & J. M. Riddoch (Eds.), Attention in action: Advances from cognitive neuroscience (pp. 109–130). Hove: Psychology Press.CrossRef
go back to reference Beckers, T., De Houwer, J., & Eelen, P. (2002). Automatic integration of non-perceptual action effect features: The case of the associative affective Simon effect. Psychological Research, 66(3), 166–173.PubMedCrossRef Beckers, T., De Houwer, J., & Eelen, P. (2002). Automatic integration of non-perceptual action effect features: The case of the associative affective Simon effect. Psychological Research, 66(3), 166–173.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Bibra, E. v., & Harleß, E. (1847). Die Wirkung des Schwefeläthers in chemischer und physiologischer Beziehung. Erlangen: Heyder. Bibra, E. v., & Harleß, E. (1847). Die Wirkung des Schwefeläthers in chemischer und physiologischer Beziehung. Erlangen: Heyder.
go back to reference Bolles, R. C. (1970). Species-specific defense reactions and avoidance learning. Psychological Review, 77(1), 32–48.CrossRef Bolles, R. C. (1970). Species-specific defense reactions and avoidance learning. Psychological Review, 77(1), 32–48.CrossRef
go back to reference Brass, M., & Haggard, P. (2008). The what, when, whether model of intentional action. Neuroscientist, 14(4), 319–325.PubMedCrossRef Brass, M., & Haggard, P. (2008). The what, when, whether model of intentional action. Neuroscientist, 14(4), 319–325.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Buttelmann, D., Carpenter, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Enculturated chimpanzees imitate rationality. Developmental Science, 10(4), F31–F38.PubMedCrossRef Buttelmann, D., Carpenter, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Enculturated chimpanzees imitate rationality. Developmental Science, 10(4), F31–F38.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Dutzi, I. B., & Hommel, B. (2009). The microgenesis of action-effect binding. Psychological Research, 73, 425–435.PubMedCrossRef Dutzi, I. B., & Hommel, B. (2009). The microgenesis of action-effect binding. Psychological Research, 73, 425–435.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Eder, A. B., Müsseler, J., & Hommel, B. (2011). The structure of affective action representations: Temporal binding of affective response codes. Psychological Research. Eder, A. B., Müsseler, J., & Hommel, B. (2011). The structure of affective action representations: Temporal binding of affective response codes. Psychological Research.
go back to reference Eenshuistra, R. M., Weidema, M. A., & Hommel, B. (2004). Development of the acquisition and control of action-effect associations. Acta Psychologica, 115, 185–209.PubMedCrossRef Eenshuistra, R. M., Weidema, M. A., & Hommel, B. (2004). Development of the acquisition and control of action-effect associations. Acta Psychologica, 115, 185–209.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Elsner, B., Hommel, B., Mentschel, C., Drzezga, A., Prinz, W., Conrad, B., et al. (2002). Linking actions and their perceivable consequences in the human brain. NeuroImage, 17(1), 364–372.PubMedCrossRef Elsner, B., Hommel, B., Mentschel, C., Drzezga, A., Prinz, W., Conrad, B., et al. (2002). Linking actions and their perceivable consequences in the human brain. NeuroImage, 17(1), 364–372.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Gerber, B., & Hendel, T. (2006). Outcome expectations drive learned behaviour in larval Drosophila. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 273, 2965–2968.PubMedCrossRef Gerber, B., & Hendel, T. (2006). Outcome expectations drive learned behaviour in larval Drosophila. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 273, 2965–2968.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Gergely, G., Bekkering, H., & Király, I. (2002). Rational imitation in preverbal infants. Nature, 415, 755.PubMedCrossRef Gergely, G., Bekkering, H., & Király, I. (2002). Rational imitation in preverbal infants. Nature, 415, 755.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Harleß, E. (1861). Der Apparat des Willens [The Apparatus of Will]. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 38(2), 50–73. Harleß, E. (1861). Der Apparat des Willens [The Apparatus of Will]. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 38(2), 50–73.
go back to reference Harleß, A. v. (Ed.). (1862). Die elementaren Funktionen der kreatürlichen Seele. München: Fleischmann’s Buchhandlung. Harleß, A. v. (Ed.). (1862). Die elementaren Funktionen der kreatürlichen Seele. München: Fleischmann’s Buchhandlung.
go back to reference Herbart, J. F. (1825). Psychologie als Wissenschaft neu gegründet auf Erfahrung, Metaphysik und Mathematik [Psychology as a science newly founded on experience, metaphysics, and mathematics]. Königsberg: August Wilhelm Unzer. Herbart, J. F. (1825). Psychologie als Wissenschaft neu gegründet auf Erfahrung, Metaphysik und Mathematik [Psychology as a science newly founded on experience, metaphysics, and mathematics]. Königsberg: August Wilhelm Unzer.
go back to reference Herwig, A., Prinz, W., & Waszak, F. (2007). Two modes of sensorimotor integration in intention-based and stimulus-based actions. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 60(11), 1540–1554.CrossRef Herwig, A., Prinz, W., & Waszak, F. (2007). Two modes of sensorimotor integration in intention-based and stimulus-based actions. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 60(11), 1540–1554.CrossRef
go back to reference Herwig, A., & Waszak, F. (2009). Intention and attention in ideomotor learning. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 62(2), 219–227.CrossRef Herwig, A., & Waszak, F. (2009). Intention and attention in ideomotor learning. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 62(2), 219–227.CrossRef
go back to reference Hoffmann, J. (1993). Vorhersage und Erkenntnis: Die Funktion von Antizipationen in der menschlichen Verhaltenssteuerung und Wahrnehmung [Prediction and Realisation: The function of anticipations in human behavioural control and perception]. Göttingen: Hogrefe. Hoffmann, J. (1993). Vorhersage und Erkenntnis: Die Funktion von Antizipationen in der menschlichen Verhaltenssteuerung und Wahrnehmung [Prediction and Realisation: The function of anticipations in human behavioural control and perception]. Göttingen: Hogrefe.
go back to reference Hoffmann, J. (2003). Anticipatory behavioral control. In M. Butz, O. Sigaud, & P. Gerard (Eds.), Anticipatory behavior in adaptive learning systems (pp. 44–65). Heidelberg: Springer.CrossRef Hoffmann, J. (2003). Anticipatory behavioral control. In M. Butz, O. Sigaud, & P. Gerard (Eds.), Anticipatory behavior in adaptive learning systems (pp. 44–65). Heidelberg: Springer.CrossRef
go back to reference Hoffmann, J., & Sebald, A. (2000). Lernmechanismen zum Erwerb verhaltenssteuernden Wissens. Psychologische Rundschau, 51(1), 1–9.CrossRef Hoffmann, J., & Sebald, A. (2000). Lernmechanismen zum Erwerb verhaltenssteuernden Wissens. Psychologische Rundschau, 51(1), 1–9.CrossRef
go back to reference Hommel, B. (2003). Acquisition and control of voluntary action. In S. Maasen, W. Prinz, & G. Roth (Eds.), Voluntary action: Brains, minds, and sociality (pp. 34–48). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hommel, B. (2003). Acquisition and control of voluntary action. In S. Maasen, W. Prinz, & G. Roth (Eds.), Voluntary action: Brains, minds, and sociality (pp. 34–48). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Hommel, B. (2004). Event files: Feature binding in and across perception and action. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 494–500.PubMedCrossRef Hommel, B. (2004). Event files: Feature binding in and across perception and action. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 494–500.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Hommel, B. (2009). Action control according to TEC (theory of event coding). Psychological Research, 73, 512–526.PubMedCrossRef Hommel, B. (2009). Action control according to TEC (theory of event coding). Psychological Research, 73, 512–526.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Hommel, B., Müsseler, J., Aschersleben, G., & Prinz, W. (2001). The theory of event coding: A framework for perception and action. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 849–878.PubMedCrossRef Hommel, B., Müsseler, J., Aschersleben, G., & Prinz, W. (2001). The theory of event coding: A framework for perception and action. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 849–878.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Jahanshahi, M., Jenkins, I. H., Brown, R. G., Marsden, C. D., Passingham, R. E., & Brooks, D. J. (1995). Self-initiated versus externally triggered movements. I. An investigation using measurement of regional cerebral blood flow with PET and movement-related potentials in normal and Parkinson’s disease subjects. Brain, 118(4), 913–933.PubMedCrossRef Jahanshahi, M., Jenkins, I. H., Brown, R. G., Marsden, C. D., Passingham, R. E., & Brooks, D. J. (1995). Self-initiated versus externally triggered movements. I. An investigation using measurement of regional cerebral blood flow with PET and movement-related potentials in normal and Parkinson’s disease subjects. Brain, 118(4), 913–933.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference James, W. (1890/1981). The principles of psychology (vol. 2). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. James, W. (1890/1981). The principles of psychology (vol. 2). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
go back to reference Janczyk, M., Pfister, R., & Kunde, W. (2011). On the persistence of tool-based compatibility effects. Journal of Psychology. Janczyk, M., Pfister, R., & Kunde, W. (2011). On the persistence of tool-based compatibility effects. Journal of Psychology.
go back to reference Janczyk, M., Skirde, S., Weigelt, M., & Kunde, W. (2009). Visual and tactile action effects determine bimanual coordination performance. Human Movement Science, 28(4), 437–449.PubMedCrossRef Janczyk, M., Skirde, S., Weigelt, M., & Kunde, W. (2009). Visual and tactile action effects determine bimanual coordination performance. Human Movement Science, 28(4), 437–449.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Karbach, J., Kray, J., & Hommel, B. (2011). Action-effect learning in early childhood: Does language matter? Psychological Research, 75, 334–340. Karbach, J., Kray, J., & Hommel, B. (2011). Action-effect learning in early childhood: Does language matter? Psychological Research, 75, 334–340.
go back to reference Kiesel, A., & Hoffmann, J. (2004). Variable action effects: Response control by context-specific effect anticipations. Psychological Research, 68, 155–162.PubMedCrossRef Kiesel, A., & Hoffmann, J. (2004). Variable action effects: Response control by context-specific effect anticipations. Psychological Research, 68, 155–162.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Kühn, S., Keizer, A. W., Rombouts, S., & Hommel, B. (2011). The functional and neural mechanism of action preparation: Roles of EBA and FFA in voluntary action control. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23(1), 214–200. Kühn, S., Keizer, A. W., Rombouts, S., & Hommel, B. (2011). The functional and neural mechanism of action preparation: Roles of EBA and FFA in voluntary action control. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23(1), 214–200.
go back to reference Kühn, S., Seurinck, R., Fias, W., & Waszak, F. (2010). The internal anticipation of sensory action effects: When action induces FFA and PPA activity. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 4(54). doi:10.3389/fnhum.2010.00054. Kühn, S., Seurinck, R., Fias, W., & Waszak, F. (2010). The internal anticipation of sensory action effects: When action induces FFA and PPA activity. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 4(54). doi:10.​3389/​fnhum.​2010.​00054.
go back to reference Kunde, W. (2001). Response-effect compatibility in manual choice reaction tasks. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 27(2), 387–394.PubMedCrossRef Kunde, W. (2001). Response-effect compatibility in manual choice reaction tasks. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 27(2), 387–394.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Kunde, W., Lozo, L., & Neumann, R. (2011). Effect-based control of facial expressions. Evidence from action-effect compatibility. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. doi: 10.3758/s13423-011-0093-x. Kunde, W., Lozo, L., & Neumann, R. (2011). Effect-based control of facial expressions. Evidence from action-effect compatibility. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. doi: 10.​3758/​s13423-011-0093-x.
go back to reference Laycock, T. (1845). On the reflex functions of the brain. British and Foreign Medical Journal, 19, 298–311. Laycock, T. (1845). On the reflex functions of the brain. British and Foreign Medical Journal, 19, 298–311.
go back to reference Leff, A. (1991). Thomas Laycock and the cerebral reflex: A function arising from and pointing to the unity of nature. History of Psychiatry, 2(8), 385–407.PubMedCrossRef Leff, A. (1991). Thomas Laycock and the cerebral reflex: A function arising from and pointing to the unity of nature. History of Psychiatry, 2(8), 385–407.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Leff, A. (2003). Thomas Laycock and the romantic genesis of the cerebral reflex. Advances in clinical neuroscience and rehabilitation, 3(1), 26–27. Leff, A. (2003). Thomas Laycock and the romantic genesis of the cerebral reflex. Advances in clinical neuroscience and rehabilitation, 3(1), 26–27.
go back to reference Lotze, H. R. (1852). Medicinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele [Medical psychology or the physiology of the mind]. Leipzig: Weidmann’sche Buchhandlung. Lotze, H. R. (1852). Medicinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele [Medical psychology or the physiology of the mind]. Leipzig: Weidmann’sche Buchhandlung.
go back to reference Martin, A. (1857). Personal-Nachrichten. Aerztliches Intelligenz-Blatt, 4(23), 296. Martin, A. (1857). Personal-Nachrichten. Aerztliches Intelligenz-Blatt, 4(23), 296.
go back to reference Melcher, T., Weidema, M., Eenshuistra, R. M., Hommel, B., & Gruber, O. (2008). The neural substrate of the ideomotor principle: An event-related fMRI analysis. NeuroImage, 39(3), 1274–1288.PubMedCrossRef Melcher, T., Weidema, M., Eenshuistra, R. M., Hommel, B., & Gruber, O. (2008). The neural substrate of the ideomotor principle: An event-related fMRI analysis. NeuroImage, 39(3), 1274–1288.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Nattkemper, D., Ziessler, M., & Frensch, P. (2010). Binding in voluntary action control. Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews, 34, 1092–1101.CrossRef Nattkemper, D., Ziessler, M., & Frensch, P. (2010). Binding in voluntary action control. Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews, 34, 1092–1101.CrossRef
go back to reference Nikolaev, A., Ziessler, M., van Leeuwen, C., & Dimova, C. (2008). Anticipated action consequences as nexus between action and perception: Evidence from event-related potentials. Biological Psychology, 78, 53–65.PubMedCrossRef Nikolaev, A., Ziessler, M., van Leeuwen, C., & Dimova, C. (2008). Anticipated action consequences as nexus between action and perception: Evidence from event-related potentials. Biological Psychology, 78, 53–65.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Pfister, R., Kiesel, A., & Hoffmann, J. (2011). Learning at any rate: Action-effect learning for stimulus-based actions. Psychological Research, 75(1), 61–65.PubMedCrossRef Pfister, R., Kiesel, A., & Hoffmann, J. (2011). Learning at any rate: Action-effect learning for stimulus-based actions. Psychological Research, 75(1), 61–65.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Pfister, R., Kiesel, A., & Melcher, T. (2010). Adaptive control of ideomotor effect anticipations. Acta Psychologica, 135(3), 316–322.PubMedCrossRef Pfister, R., Kiesel, A., & Melcher, T. (2010). Adaptive control of ideomotor effect anticipations. Acta Psychologica, 135(3), 316–322.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Randolph, B. A. D. (1986). Spacial pecking relations and the expression of atonal auditory behavior. New York: Confederation Press. Randolph, B. A. D. (1986). Spacial pecking relations and the expression of atonal auditory behavior. New York: Confederation Press.
go back to reference Shin, Y. K., Proctor, R. W., & Capaldi, E. J. (2010). A review of contemporary ideomotor theory. Psychological Bulletin, 136(6), 943–974.PubMedCrossRef Shin, Y. K., Proctor, R. W., & Capaldi, E. J. (2010). A review of contemporary ideomotor theory. Psychological Bulletin, 136(6), 943–974.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Stock, A., & Hoffmann, J. (2002). Intentional fixation of behavioural learning, or how R-O learning blocks S-R learning. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 14, 127–153.CrossRef Stock, A., & Hoffmann, J. (2002). Intentional fixation of behavioural learning, or how R-O learning blocks S-R learning. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 14, 127–153.CrossRef
go back to reference Stock, A., & Stock, C. (2004). A short history of ideomotor action. Psychological Research, 68, 176–188.PubMedCrossRef Stock, A., & Stock, C. (2004). A short history of ideomotor action. Psychological Research, 68, 176–188.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Unschuld, P. (Ed.). (1989). 50 Jahre Institut für Geschichte der Medizin der Universität München [50 years of the institute for the history of medicine at the University of Munich]. München: Cygnus. Unschuld, P. (Ed.). (1989). 50 Jahre Institut für Geschichte der Medizin der Universität München [50 years of the institute for the history of medicine at the University of Munich]. München: Cygnus.
go back to reference Verschoor, S. A., Weidema, M., Biro, S., & Hommel, B. (2010). Where do action goals come from? Evidence for spontaneous action-effect binding in infants. Frontiers in Psychology, 1, (201). doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2010.00201 Verschoor, S. A., Weidema, M., Biro, S., & Hommel, B. (2010). Where do action goals come from? Evidence for spontaneous action-effect binding in infants. Frontiers in Psychology, 1, (201). doi: 10.​3389/​fpsyg.​2010.​00201
go back to reference Waszak, F., & Herwig, A. (2007). Effect anticipation modulates deviance processing in the brain. Brain Research, 1183, 74–82.PubMedCrossRef Waszak, F., & Herwig, A. (2007). Effect anticipation modulates deviance processing in the brain. Brain Research, 1183, 74–82.PubMedCrossRef
go back to reference Wolfensteller, U., & Ruge, H. (2011). On the timescale of stimulus-based action-effect learning. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology. Wolfensteller, U., & Ruge, H. (2011). On the timescale of stimulus-based action-effect learning. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology.
go back to reference Wolpert, D. M., & Kawato, M. (1998). Multiple paired forward and inverse models for motor control. Neural Networks, 11, 1317–1329.PubMedCrossRef Wolpert, D. M., & Kawato, M. (1998). Multiple paired forward and inverse models for motor control. Neural Networks, 11, 1317–1329.PubMedCrossRef
Metagegevens
Titel
Harleß’ Apparatus of Will: 150 years later
Auteurs
Roland Pfister
Markus Janczyk
Publicatiedatum
01-09-2012
Uitgeverij
Springer-Verlag
Gepubliceerd in
Psychological Research / Uitgave 5/2012
Print ISSN: 0340-0727
Elektronisch ISSN: 1430-2772
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00426-011-0362-3

Andere artikelen Uitgave 5/2012

Psychological Research 5/2012 Naar de uitgave