Introduction
When humans voluntarily act to cause a change in their environment and the intended change eventually presents itself a sense of agency for the action as well as the outcome arises (Haggard & Tsakiris,
2009). Studies have shown that the interval between such voluntary actions and subsequent action–effects is perceived as shortened compared to identical intervals caused by involuntary movements or third parties (Buehner & Humphreys,
2009; Haggard et al.,
2002). This perceived shortening of the interval is referred to as temporal binding or intentional binding (for a review see Moore & Obhi,
2012). There is good reason to believe that outcomes which the agent has intended and therefore predicted are perceived somewhat differently than randomly occurring events in the environment. Consequently, temporal binding is widely employed as an implicit measure for sense of agency even though it is debated whether it is fair to do so (for a critical review see Buehner,
2012; Kirsch et al.,
2019; Thanopoulos et al.,
2018). Temporal binding is susceptible to various factors such as valence (Christensen et al.,
2016; Moreton et al.,
2017; Takahata et al.,
2012) and control (Beck et al.,
2017) just to name a few and relates to the sense of agency a person has in a specific situation. Other strands of research have focused on the origin of temporal binding as either a phenomenon of mere causality or as product of multisensory integration (Hoerl et al.,
2020; Klaffehn et al.,
2021). Finally, all this research converges on the observation that the interval between an action and a causally linked sensory event is perceived as shortened in comparison to identical intervals lacking causal or intentional links. Up-close, the perceived shortening is typically comprised of a forward shift of the action towards the sensory event and a backward shift of the sensory event towards the preceding action (for a discussion of time awareness of sensory events see Tsakiris & Haggard,
2005).
While the self and self-conception are at the center of the sense of agency, research in the field has mainly concentrated on the self-relevance of the action, i.e., whether an action was voluntary or involuntary (Haggard & Clark,
2003), whether it was freely chosen or forced (Caspar et al.,
2018), and whether it was executed by the actor or not (Pfister et al.,
2014). Other studies analyzed the effect of joint actions on the sense of agency in human–human pairings or in human–machine interactions (for a review on social agency, see Silver et al.,
2021). Surprisingly, thus far little research has been published on the self-relevance of action–effects.
Self-relevant information is processed faster and reactions to self-relevant stimuli are less error-prone than reactions to stimuli which have not been associated with the self (Sui et al.,
2012). In experiments probing the self-prioritization effect, participants are asked, mostly by instruction, to associate a random geometric shape with themselves, another one with a friend, and a third one with a stranger. Afterwards, they complete a classification task in which participants see a shape label pairing and have to decide whether shape and label match. Typically, responses in self-match trials are fastest and least error-prone (Sui et al.,
2012). Self-prioritization has also been found for arbitrary ownership (Constable et al.,
2019; Cunningham et al.,
2008) in combination with valence and reward (Golubickis et al.,
2021; Sui & Humphreys,
2015). It also extends to other outcome domains such as auditory and tactile stimuli (Schäfer et al.,
2016) as well as generalized concepts, i.e., a music instrument presented visually or auditory, or a shape with varying characteristics (Schäfer et al.,
2015). Self-related objects are not only processed faster but also perceived to be more valuable (Kahneman et al.,
1991). Thus, Humphreys and Sui (
2016) proposed a neural network of personal significance in which areas for self-referential processing interact with areas of attentional control (see Sui et al.,
2013). Self-relevance speeds up the focusing of attention during decision making such that when self-relevant information is processed, the attentional spotlight narrows in on them a lot faster than when a target is not self-related (Golubickis & Macrae,
2021b). Self-prioritization does, however, not only reside on a central stage influencing attention and action selection, rather it also influences movement production and execution (Constable et al.,
2011; Desebrock & Spence,
2021; Desebrock et al.,
2018). Consequently, it seems plausible to assume that actions involving a higher degree of agency should, conversely, also be conceived as more self-relevant than simple automated acts (Wegner,
2002). But is this link bidirectional? Does a higher degree of self-relevance also lead to a stronger sense of agency?
Makwana and Srinivasan (
2019) were the first to address this question with an interval estimation task. Participants’ keypresses produced either stimuli which were previously associated with the self or a friend or a stranger. Subsequently, they were asked to estimate the duration of the interval between the keypress and the appearance of one of the three stimuli. Results showed that temporal binding was stronger, i.e., the interval perceived as shorter, when participants produced stimuli associated with the self as compared to stimuli associated with a friend or a stranger. Chiarella et al. (
2020) extended these findings and suggest that promoting self-other connections e.g., through meditation, eliminates advantages of self-referential processing in postdictive temporal binding (binding caused by observation of a just encountered action–effect episode) but not the early process of self-prioritization.
One crucial shortcoming of the employed method is that it is impossible to discern whether the perceived shortening of the interval stems from a perceptual shift of the action towards the action–effect or a shift of the action–effect towards the action or a reciprocal attraction. Temporal binding is comprised of action binding (perceived later point in time of an action that produces an action–effect compared to an action that does not) and effect binding (perceived earlier point in time of an event that was produced by an action compared to an event that was not). Action binding and effect binding might be shaped by different processes (Hon,
2023; Tanaka et al., 2019) and increases in one component can be associated with decreases in the other (Lush et al.,
2019; Wolpe et al.,
2013; Yamamoto,
2020). Empirically, action binding and effect binding are uncorrelated across participants (Tonn et al., (
2021) calling for separate analyses of the two rather than a composite measure like interval estimation.
Regarding self-relevance, there is reason to speculate that self-relevant stimuli impact effect binding and action binding differently. For example, if self-relevant stimuli get more attention than other-related stimuli they are perhaps accessible earlier to the system, thereby prompting stronger effect binding. Alternatively, devoting attention to a stimulus likely also increases reliability (or conversely reduces noise) of processing these stimuli, including processing of the stimulus’ timepoint. Action binding and effect binding have been shown to reflect the reliability processing differences of these two events, with larger binding effects for the relatively less reliable event (Klaffehn et al.,
2021). Thus, self-relevant stimuli might be processed with higher levels of reliability than other-relevant stimuli, whereby action binding might increase.
To conclude there are methodical and theoretical reasons to have a look at the impact of self-relevance using a different measure, i.e., the Libet clock, which is what the present study intended to do.
General discussion
The present line of research contributes to temporal binding research as well as research on self-prioritization while at the same time bringing the two together. While theorizing as well as preliminary evidence suggest that self-related outcomes produce stronger temporal binding than other-related outcomes, we did not find any influence of self-relevance on temporal binding. In all four experiments, our manipulation checks, i.e., replicating the self-prioritization effect, were reasonably successful. Note, however, that the matching phase was fairly short in comparison to typical self-prioritization studies. We manipulated action–effect modality as well as its salience and its predictability but none of these manipulations proved to have an influence on temporal binding. Nonetheless, we did find significant effect binding in all four individual experiments and action binding in all but the first experiment. We propose two possible mechanisms how self-relevance and temporal binding influence each other. First, self-relevance might only influence temporal binding via immediate response selection. Second, simply being the cause for external events might be sufficient for these events to gain self-relevance.
Research on temporal binding for visual action–effects using the Libet clock is scarce as both time reference and effect are presented in the same modality which might result in reduced salience of action–effects (Moretto et al.,
2011; Ruess et al.,
2018; but see e.g., Nolden et al.,
2012 for visual action–effects and interval estimations). In addition, subjective time perception of visual outcomes could be subject to resolution constrains as the speeds of the pacemakers differ between the visual and auditory domain (Wearden et al.,
1998). Our results add to this body of literature by showing that temporal binding for visual action–effects can indeed be measured with the clock method (Experiment 1 and Experiment 2). In addition, the (null-)effects observed for visual stimuli were no different to those we observed with auditory outcomes.
The results presented here seem to contradict those of the original study by Makwana and Srinivasan (
2019) and its replication (Chiarella et al.,
2020). Reasons for this are manifold and there are a few non-trivial differences in the study design that might account for the diverging results. First, we measured temporal binding with the Libet clock to (a) be able to examine perceived action shifts and action–effect shifts separately and (b) minimize demand effects that might occur when participants retrospectively judge the interval between their action and a specific outcome. Demand characteristics seem to bias interval estimations more easily than the assessment of time perception via the Libet clock. Comparing time estimations between different conditions makes the method more opaque and thus harder to influence. This notion, that interval estimations might be influenced by other high-level processes than time judgements made with the Libet clock, is strengthened by a recent study showing a divergence in these two measures (Siebertz & Jansen,
2022). Consequently, the two measures might be manifestations of different agency experiences where action selection but not action execution is linked to explicit knowledge (see also Hemed et al.,
2022; Karsh et al.,
2020).
Second, the two previous studies emphasized the self-other reference also during the temporal binding task by asking participants each trial whether the shape they had just produced was associated with the self, a friend, or a stranger. We reduced such influences by simply asking for the identity of the shape (or tone) after every fourth trial and thereby ensured that participants did pay attention to the identity of the action–effect. However, this should not have reduced the strength of the self-relevance manipulation as it facilitates performance as long as a self-relevant dimension, in this case identity of the shape, is part of the task set (Falbén et al.,
2019).
Third, the previous studies employed varying delays as an inherent feature of the interval estimation method and the most salient difference between individual identity categories was observed when the outcome was delayed by 400 ms. In the present study, we opted for a constant delay of 250 ms which might not be quite comparable as to the ambiguity it creates for the sensorimotor evaluation of agency. Varying delays may lead to higher ambiguity for sensorimotor evaluation and thus favor high-level cues, in this case stimulus identity, to determine feelings of agency. Consequently, the short delay in the present study would have been an unambiguous (low-level) signal of agency, granting less weight to the high-level cue.
Fourth, while time intervals can technically be inferred from differences in time points, time intervals and time points constitute two perceptually different events. It might well be that certain factors can shape the perception of time intervals, as used by Makwana and Srinivasan (
2019), but not time points, as used in the present study. Future research should consider this by varying the delays between action and outcome, and by reading out different perceptual aspects of the same physical events from the same participants.
Finally, in the present study, participants performed the temporal binding task as well as the matching task in one session, whereas Makwana and Srinivasan (
2019) invited participants to the lab twice—once for a longer matching session and once to complete a short matching block followed by the interval estimation task. While this elongated period might have strengthened the association between the self and the arbitrary stimulus, data of our matching task clearly showed, that participants were able to pick up a strong association in the time provided. Consequently, we conjecture that the varying levels of induction of self-relevance are a less likely explanation of the diverging result patterns rather than other possible causes such as weaker demand effects in the current temporal binding measure than in the interval estimation procedure used in previous studies.
As we could not replicate previous findings, the question must be raised whether there is an effect of self-relevance on temporal binding at all. As of yet, there is no clear answer to this question, but we propose two arguments to explain the lack of influence of self-relevance on temporal binding in the present study. This opens new perspectives for future research in the field.
First, stimulus processing and response selection possibly moderate the influence of self-relevance on temporal binding. Initially, Humphreys and Sui (
2016) argued that the self-prioritization effect stems from an early processing bias in attentional control towards self-related information. However, Schäfer et al. (
2020) could show that other information such as negative valence can derail attention at an earlier stage indicating that self-related information does not trump mere perceptual input. In line with this, the lack of stronger temporal binding of self-relevant action–effects suggests that self-related stimuli are not processed faster perceptually, compared to other-related stimuli. That is, the estimation errors for both effect-occurrences (self-related and other-related) were equal, even though participants reacted faster and more accurately to self-match trials compared to other-match trials in the matching task. This suggests that the self-prioritization effect does not reflect perceptual benefits of self-related stimuli, i.e., earlier perception, but rather advantages in later/other processing stages such as response selection or response execution, in case such selection is required. Consequently, the expected modulation might occur if the identity of the outcome is required to generate an appropriate motor response to this outcome indicating prioritization in the anticipation of self-relevant action–effects (e.g., Kunde,
2001; Pfister et al.,
2010). This idea is supported by Woźniak and Knoblich (
2021) who suggest that the self-association has to be active in working memory to elicit a self-prioritization effect Additional work indicates that the automaticity of self-prioritization is conditional to attention on the self-relevance of the object to be classified (Caughey et al.,
2021; Falbén et al.,
2019). Neither previous studies nor the current study design allow to test this mechanism. Hence, to further resolve the puzzle whether self-relevance influences temporal binding, future research could interlace the temporal binding and self-prioritization task in such a way that temporal binding is measured in combination with continuous speeded responses.
Second, causing external events might suffice for these to become self-relevant. The specific setup of the current studies caters to this explanation. Knowing that an event is going to occur and even being able to predict its nature and timing helps the organism to prepare for this specific event. Thus, it will be expected and carry relevance. In contrast to the matching task, where the stimulus-label combination serves as symbol to trigger an action that must be retrieved from memory, in the temporal binding task, the stimulus serves as action–effect. Here, participants retrospectively have to retrieve the timing as well as the identity (for unpredictable outcomes) of the perceived sensory input to make judgements about its occurrence (see Moore & Haggard,
2008; Reddy,
2022). Attention focusses more quickly on self-relevant stimuli (see also Golubickis & Macrae,
2021b) making them accessible earlier to the system whereby effect binding should increase. Yet, such speeded attentional focusing might only occur with immediate action planning but not with retrospective judgements of sensory events. In the same vein, Golubickis et al. (
2017) found temporal influences on the self-prioritization effect such that only stimuli associated with the current self, as compared to a future or past self, facilitated reaction times and accuracy indicating that the attentional benefit of self-relevant information is timely limited. Knowing whether a sensory event in the outside world was caused by oneself or not is crucial for human learning and development throughout all stages of life (Engbert & Wohlschläger,
2007; Kunde et al.,
2018; Schaaf et al.,
2022). Thus, an agent’s knowledge of their effectiveness in causing a certain outcome might be enough for this specific event to gain self-relevance. In consequence, stimuli which have previously been associated with someone else become self-relevant, too, just by the fact that they were caused by an own motor action. Hence, the lack of influence of the outcome’s self-relevance on temporal binding. One possibility to address this would be to reduce participants’ effectiveness, e.g., by introducing longer action–outcome delays, by varying action–outcome contingency, or by increasing causal uncertainty through other agents. In these cases, the outcome’s self-relevance provides additional information about the agent’s efficiency and might thus facilitate temporal binding.
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.