The American Psychiatric Association (APA) has updated its Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including with new information specifically addressed to individuals in the European Economic Area. As described in the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, this website utilizes cookies, including for the purpose of offering an optimal online experience and services tailored to your preferences.

Please read the entire Privacy Policy and Terms of Use. By closing this message, browsing this website, continuing the navigation, or otherwise continuing to use the APA's websites, you confirm that you understand and accept the terms of the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including the utilization of cookies.

×
Other ArticleFull Access

Overcoming Social Amnesia: The Role for a Social Perspective in Psychiatric Research and Practice

Published Online:https://doi.org/10.1176/ps.51.1.72

Abstract

Psychiatry's reliance on biological models has resulted increasingly in the social realm's being dismissed or trivialized. The author examines the adverse consequences of this situation for psychiatric research and practice and suggests methods for addressing the problem. He describes how the social perspective has been extruded from discussions about the definition, future, and accomplishments of psychiatry, and he reviews four areas in which the biological model has produced unvalidated assumptions about the etiology, course, and prevention of mental disorders. The author shows how the social realm is intrinsic to concepts of mind and mental illness, and he describes seven ways in which a social perspective can provide a complement or a corrective to the prevailing assumptions of biological models, indicate new points of departure, and suggest methods for psychiatry's expansion.

The extrusion of the social realm from psychiatric discourse has been most apparent in discussions about the definition, future, and accomplishments of psychiatry. In an editorial in the American Journal of Psychiatry entitled "What Is Psychiatry?" Andreasen (1) defined psychiatry as the medical specialty that treats disorders of the mind. Mind is described as "an expression of the activity of the brain." Similarly, Kandel (2), in a lead article in the same journal, wrote that "all mental processes… derive from operations of the brain."

Although these writers may not have fully intended it, their statements strongly suggest that the mind is merely a reflection of the workings of the brain. The social constituency of the mind is omitted. Similarly, in recent years, a spate of articles have appeared on the future of psychiatry, and most have leaned heavily on the biomedical side of diagnosis and treatment (3,4,5,6,7). For example, Lieberman and Rush (3) called for redefining psychiatry as a "clinical neuroscience."

Numerous examples exist of how the biomedicalization of psychiatry is increasingly omitting or, at best, trivializing the social components of research and practice. This state of affairs has potentially serious consequences for research and practice. Therefore, in this article, I first describe how the social world is relevant to psychiatry. Next, I illustrate how the biomedicalization of psychiatry has produced a variety of unvalidated assumptions about the etiology, course, and prevention of mental disorders. I then show how a serious re-engagement of the social realm in research and practice can provide a complement or corrective to these assumptions, adumbrate new points of departure, and suggest methods for psychiatry's expansion.

Definitions

Although an aim of this paper is to demonstrate that the "social" inheres within the biological and psychological realms, it is useful to begin with some definitions. Thus I use the word "social" to refer to aspects of the life, welfare, and relations of humans in a community. "Psychological" pertains to human behavior and mental states and processes. "Biological" refers to aspects of living organisms such as structure and physiological processes. "Biomedical" comprises aspects of the biological and physiological sciences that relate to or underlie medicine.

How the social world is relevant to psychiatry

"Mental" and "mental illness" are social concepts

Although Kandel (2) correctly observed that "all mental processes are biological," he failed to add that all higher mental processes are also social and contextually bound. Terms that we use for mental processes such as fear, anxiety, pleasure, attention, memory, mood, and so forth are not biological but social concepts. They are intrinsically tied to the way people relate to each other (8). Cognition, memory, perception, emotion, and anxiety vary considerably from one culture or historical period to another (9,10,11). Culture is not "out there" to be treated as an independent variable, but something that impinges on a person's thinking (12).

Thus, although it is typically assumed that there are distinct, objectively existing entities that correspond to the various categories of the mind, these categories have always depended on the use to which they were put in specific social contexts (13). Mental processes must always be social, just as they must always be biologically situated because they occur in biological beings. Both are necessary; neither is sufficient.

Diagnoses in psychiatry are starkly different from diagnoses in physical medicine in which asymptomatic or incidental disorders are often uncovered, such as an examination of the prostate that reveals a malignancy. To use a biological marker to define a mental illness would mean that we must be willing to accept a definition based on an incidental abnormality that might be found on neuroimaging, even if the subject never manifested any symptoms. Simply put, is it logical to define a contented person as "depressed" based on an abnormality in brain functioning?

Indeed, we can create new disease categories based on brain findings, but these categories would no longer rely on mental concepts and therefore cannot be mental disorders. Because mental symptoms involve verbal communications and behaviors—that is, cultural understandings—psychiatric illness can never be transmuted into an anatomical or physiological entity in the same way as physical illness. As Satel (14) wrote about addiction, "You can examine brains all day, but you'd never call anyone an addict unless he acted like one."

Social forces transform biological and psychological structures

Evidence is accumulating that social and environmental forces can directly influence neural functioning, synaptic connections, gene transcription, ventricular size, and neurotransmitters (15,16,17,18,19,20). Analogous changes occur at the psychological level. Many years ago, the Russian developmental psychologist Vygotsky concluded that a person's "psychological nature represents an aggregate of social relations that have been transformed internally and that have become functions of personality and forms of structure" (21). Luria (22) further recognized that not only the content but also the actual form of psychological processes, including "higher, specifically human forms of psychological activity such as voluntary attention, active memory, and (especially) abstract thought" are altered with changes in social structures.

Social forces can alter psychiatric disorders

Cochrane (23) observed that "the fluctuations in the incidence of disorders over time, place, and social category are too large to be explained away by the differential incidence of purely biomedical imbalance." A variety of social factors have been implicated in affecting the incidence and outcome of menta1 illness. For example, social class, gender, marital status, unemployment, housing conditions, social stressors, life events, social supports, and immigrant status have all been linked to psychological ill health, often in a complex, interactive way (24).

Considerable data support historical changes in the incidence of various psychiatric disorders such as anorexia and depression, both of which have increased during the 20th century (24,25,26). Although most psychiatric disorders are thought to be universal, the prevalence rates of disorders vary considerably (24). Thus the World Health Organization Collaborative Study on Psychological Problems found that among 15 centers worldwide, the prevalence of ICD-10 psychiatric disorders ranged from 8 percent to 53 percent (27). Rates of specific psychiatric disorders varied across sites; for example, rates of depression ranged from 2.6 percent to 15.9 percent. The content and form of disorders also vary cross-culturally. Rates of visual hallucinations are higher among persons with schizophrenia who live in developing countries (28). Susser and colleagues (29) observed that "the varieties of human affliction owe as much to the inventiveness of culture as they do to the vagaries of nature."

Finally, the outcome and course of a disorder, once defined, are influenced by social forces. For example, the outcome of depression has been found to be influenced by social support, employment, and coping styles (30). Persons with schizophrenia from lower socioeconomic classes have worse long-term outcomes in developed nations than in developing countries (31,32).

Biomedical models and the benefits of a social perspective

In the absence of a strong complementary social component, biomedical models in psychiatry have been girded by various assumptions, the validity of which remains an open question. In this section, I describe some of the principal assumptions of the biomedical models and show how a social perspective can modify, complement, or provide a useful alternative to prevailing models.

A social perspective and Cartesian modeling

Despite dramatic strides in molecular research, efforts to integrate biological elements into aspects of human psychology have been hampered by ignorance about the processes by which such integration can occur. On one hand, it is recognized that the complex chemical reactions induced by a gene, mediated through an intricate series of life circumstances, does not equal an identification between a complex human behavior and a gene (33). On the other hand, because of the inchoate state of our knowledge, researchers typically use simplified models based on the Cartesian notion that the whole is the sum of separate, irreducible, unchanging parts (34). For example, to explain a personality trait, biological and social variables may be added together in a large multivariate analysis.

In the absence of a strong, sophisticated social component in psychiatric research, no countervailing forces to various forms of biological overdeterminism have existed. In one type of analysis, several biological variables and a few basic social variables—typically race, gender, and education—are entered into an analytic model. Limiting or simplifying the social variables attenuates their effect on the outcome variable as well as their potential to detect interactions with the biological variables.

In a second type of analysis, social variables are discarded altogether. For instance, using the modeling described above, investigators of genetic influence on human behavior, or heritability, assume that genetic and environmental elements are both additive and uncorrelated (35). If these assumptions are correct, then it is permissible to look solely at heritability and assume that anything not explained is due to environment, even though no social variables are actually measured. One byproduct of this approach has been to implicate inherited particles within the individual—atoms of behavioral propensity—to explain a particular disorder or behavior (33). Statements that a behavior or disorder is 55 percent genetic and 45 percent environmental are increasingly common and represent reductionistic thinking based on an atomistic assumption of human behavior (33).

A broader and more sophisticated social research component is needed to provide complementary variables for these analyses as well as to provide detailed descriptions of the environments from which samples are recruited. With respect to the former, social variables may modify effects attributed to biomedical variables. To cite an illustration from my own research, I found that among older persons with schizophrenia, findings about the impact of positive symptoms on depression were modified by adding to the analysis several social network variables, including network member interconnectivity and proportion of members providing material assistance (36). Merely examining the relationships between clinical variables would not have adequately explained the depressive symptoms of older persons with schizophrenia nor have taken into account the interactions between depression, positive symptoms, and these social network variables.

Likewise, with respect to environmental effects, it has been customary in twin adoption studies to assume that different family environments are not correlated with each other. However, environments are often quite similar, especially within a single country or group of countries. For instance, height might be deemed nearly entirely genetic in the United States but considered socioeconomically based in Bangladesh.

Although it is a step forward to include social variables in analyses, it is also critical to move beyond global social variables such as race or income to develop more nuanced variables. Thus it is now recognized that race may be a proxy for a variety of social experiences that affect health such as access to goods and services; residential segregation, including quality of housing and exposure to environmental factors; access to labor markets; political power; and belief systems (37). Similarly, income may not be as important as accumulated wealth, levels of neighborhood wealth, the number of persons being supported by an income, the level of social deprivation, socioeconomic status in childhood, or the method used for demarcating poverty, such as deciles, quartiles, or poverty level (38).

The inclusion of social variables does not immediately obviate the limitations of Cartesian atomistic modeling, although a deepened understanding of the relationship between biological and social variables should further the development of process models. Clearly, without such social research, no substantial progress can be made.

A social perspective and the disease model of biology

Although the decision to render symptom clusters into psychopathological categories unquestionably has increased nosological conformity and improved communication among clinicians and researchers (39), it has created a variety of problems that can be adequately addressed only by the inclusion of a social perspective in research and practice.

Biology does not necessarily have priority over social perspectives in explaining mental disorders. Little empirical support has been found for strict DSM-IV boundaries (40). As Kleinman (41) observed, "The difference between 3 and 4 'vegetative' complaints is the difference between becoming a case of depression as a disease or being an instance where depression is a socially caused type of human misery. DSM-III was not created with such problems in mind, but it is applied in such settings."

Consequently, mental illness, which was developed as an analogue to physical illness, is increasingly viewed as an underlying biological (brain) entity rather than a clustering of symptoms. Andreasen (42) wrote, "Psychiatry now recognizes that serious mental illnesses are diseases in the same sense that cancer or high blood pressure are diseases. Mental illnesses are diseases that affect the brain, which is an organ of the body just as the heart or stomach is. People who suffer from mental illness suffer from a sick or broken brain, not from weak will, laziness, bad character, or bad upbringing."

An unfortunate confusion has been created by the legitimate need to avoid the Cartesian dualism of mind and spirit in which diseases of the mind are seen as diseases of the brain (43). However, what is not always recognized in biomedical models is that psychological and social aspects of the mind are not spiritual but are likewise material states. They represent a different mode of discourse for addressing how the mind is organized. Just as physical reality can be explained only in part by physics and requires chemistry for further clarification, biology cannot fully explain the mind and requires social and psychological discourses, although the latter should be consistent with biology.

Dichotomizing mental symptoms into "disease" and "nondisease" does not mean that nonbiological factors are less important than biological ones or that biology has explanatory superiority over other ways of understanding the mind and its problems (43). In some instances, biological factors may account for proportionately more of the etiology; however, this is a researchable question that will not be satisfactorily addressed by prematurely excluding social variables from analyses.

Psychopathology cannot be divorced from social context. The psychopathology model is also prone toward decontextualizing mental disorders, and a social perspective can correct this tendency. One type of decontextualization occurs when social concomitants of a disorder are attributed to the underlying features of the illness. Thus among persons with schizophrenia who are homeless, homelessness is attributed primarily to their mental disorganization rather than to the lack of affordable housing or inadequate incomes (44).

Another type of decontextualization occurs when social concomitants of an illness are not considered relevant to the fundamental structure of the disorder. Thus although many persons with schizophrenia live in poverty or have near-poverty levels of income, few studies have examined the role that poverty plays in affecting symptomatology, course, and outcome of the disorder (45).

A third type of decontextualization involves the propensity to focus on individual risk factors and proximal causation—that is, factors for which a "biological plausibility" can be argued—and to neglect or minimize the social context of such risk factors (46). For example, investigators may examine the neurodevelopmental changes predisposing to schizophrenia, the structural brain abnormalities associated with various mental disorders, or the individual stressful circumstances that precipitate a disease episode. However, they fail to examine why people come to be exposed to risk or protective factors and fail to explore the social conditions under which individual risk factors are related to the disorder.

In other words, we must ask what it is about persons' lives that might shape their exposure to neurodevelopmental, brain, or stressful risk factors. Without comprehending the context that leads to a risk, the responsibility for alleviating this risk falls on the individual, and nothing is done to alter the more fundamental factors that put people at risk of risks (46).

The structure of a disorder is not necessarily more important than its content. Kleinman (41) observed that the model of pathogeneity-pathoplasticity "comes fairly close to being a professional orthodoxy." In this model, biology is presumed to "determine" the cause and structure of the disorder, while cultural and social factors, at most, "shape" or "influence" the content of disorder. Thus paranoid schizophrenia is a biological disorder in which the content of delusions varies between cultures. Similarly, the extensive somatic symptoms accompanying depression in some cultures are merely viewed as epiphenomena of the underlying biological disorder. However, no evidence exists that content is any more or less biological than structure. Certainly, strong evidence suggests that the "epiphenomenal" expressions of physical disorders, such as physical pain in arthritis, may be more potent determinants of disability and outcome than the so-called underlying disorder (41).

Moreover, even if there were an underlying biological disorder, it is likely to be transformed at least in part by social content because the latter can transform the circuitry of the brain. An example that tends to bolster this argument is that both the form and content of schizophrenia have changed historically—there are now fewer cases of hebephrenia and catatonia and more paranoid and undifferentiated cases (32). It is here that social research can elaborate on the precise role that content plays on the outcome and course of disorders.

A disease model should not preclude prevention and public health approaches. During the 1960s, a combination of economic and sociopolitical conditions favored the development of the community psychiatry movement, which made prevention of mental illness one of its goals. However, by the late 1970s two prominent psychiatrists, Lamb and Zusman (47), baldly stated that "there is no evidence that it is possible to strengthen 'mental health' and thereby increase resistance to mental illness by general preventive activities." They maintained that "the cause and effect relationship between social conditions and mental illness is extremely questionable'' and that "mental illness is probably in large part genetically determined and it is probably not preventable, at most only modifiable. Even that it can be modified is questioned by many and there is little hard evidence one way or the other."

Lamb and Zusman's argument (47) was based on the assumption that mental illness is analogous to physical disease. In their paper they sharply distinguished between "real" mental illness and emotional distress, and they likewise assumed that psychopathology cannot be prevented unless the specific organic cause of the mental disorder is identified. However, as previously noted, the term "mental illness" has been used analogously to "physical illness," but it is not identical to physical illness. Further, even with physical illness, the role of the social environment has been increasingly recognized as enhancing susceptibility to disease (48,49). Cassel (48) showed that psychosocial stress heightens general susceptibility to illness and concluded that "a remarkably similar set of social circumstances characterize people who develop tuberculosis and schizophrenia, become alcoholic, are victims of multiple accidents, or commit suicide. Common to all these people is a marginal status in society."

It is now appreciated that many social factors have general effects on disease and that singular, one-to-one correlations are unlikely to be identified. For example, Link and Phelan (50) have described "fundamental social causes" of disease, which involve resources like knowledge, money, power, prestige, and social connections that strongly influence people's ability to avoid risks and minimize the consequences of disease once it occurs. Because of the very general utility of these social and economic resources, fundamental causes are linked to multiple disease outcomes through multiple risk-factor mechanisms.

Regardless of what the profile of diseases and known risks happen to be at any given time, those who have greater access to critical economic and social resources will be less affected by disease. On a biological level this situation may mean that those with fewer resources may experience greater social-environmental stressors, which in turn diminish host resistance, perhaps through effects on hormonal response. In any case, such effects are likely to be general across various disorders, both mental and physical.

A focus on psychopathology should not exclude positive mental health. Despite some resistance, much of the health field has moved away from treating only disability and from defining health as the absence of disease and has moved toward improving robustness. For example, Rowe and Kahn (51) described "usual" versus "successful aging." That is, persons who exercise regularly, have strong social supports, and have more personal autonomy seem to exceed age norms on various physiological and psychological measures. The emergence of a new journal, the Journal of Happiness Studies, suggests that there is increasing interest and a body of research that looks at positive mental health rather than disease.

Psychiatry's focus on the disease model favors theories of pathogenesis based on biological deficits rather than positive attributes or strengths. For example, the proportionately greater number of women who develop schizophrenia in later life is attributed to a reduction in estrogen production or a neurodegenerative process (52,53). Using a socially oriented paradigm, one might hypothesize that psychosocial factors exist that protect older men from schizophrenia, such as their greater economic resources, their higher levels of autonomy and social power, or their greater likelihood of being married (nonwidowed).

Psychopathology does not require an underlying biological abnormality, and "toxic" environments must also be examined. The psychopathology model, with its emphasis on an underlying biological deficit, has also influenced our way of looking at how genes determine mental illness. The predominant paradigm is that abnormal genes produce mental disorders. Franche (43) observed that once we recognize that the heritability of psychopathology may be due to nonpathological traits and "normal'' wiring, the exploration of social factors becomes more critical.

For example, while fair-skinned people are more susceptible to sunburn, there is nothing pathological about having fair skin, and there is no gene for sunburn. Similarly, we do not know whether a genetic relationship with psychopathology represents a biological abnormality or a biologically well-integrated set of systems that under specifiable conditions results in distress. Therefore, genetic correlations do not tell us much unless we examine the role of environmental conditions in which genes are operating.

In a similar fashion, it is also possible that a "toxic" environment produces mental distress, and that genes and other biological factors enhance well-being by modifying the toxic effects of the environment on persons. Thus, while the disease model assumes an abnormal gene for abnormal behavior, this assumption is surely not the only way to approach this issue. Here again, more fully engaging the social world opens up alternative paradigms and new points of departure.

A social perspective and the technical approach to mental illness

As psychiatry has tried to replicate the natural sciences by turning toward what Habermas (54) described as "technical control," the cultural and moral dimensions of life have been collapsed into merely technical and instrumental considerations, or "value-neutral" knowledge. Although this approach may enhance our control or mastery over events and things, it also potentially undermines our ability to adequately assess the value of our ends and the social ideology underlying these values.

The psychiatric literature has virtually ignored the postmodernist debates that have engaged the academy, the media, and, at least to some extent, psychology and psychoanalysis (55,56,57). The postmodernist challenge has been directed at mainstream science and empiricist foundationalism—that there must be a guarantee of universal reason and truth—by emphasizing that language and knowledge do not copy, reflect, or reproduce reality, but rather, that language constitutes reality (58). Consequently, each language constructs specific aspects of reality in its own way, which is rooted in specific culture and community. Thus knowledge is saturated with perspectives that reflect aspects of culture and society (11). It further follows that because the object of study is not directly reproduced, a culture of science must also exist, with a distinct body of language, concepts, and values that interprets its objects of study.

Howard (59) observed that "although philosophers of science still debate the role of values in scientific research, the controversy is no longer about whether values influence scientific practice, but rather how values are embedded in and shape scientific practice." For example, Prilleltensky (60) described a variety of values and assumptions that underlie psychological theory and practice. Values may include how much a particular clinical approach or research agenda promotes caring and compassion, human diversity, collaboration and participation, and distributive justice. Assumptions implicit in various frameworks include notions of the good life, the good society, relationships regarding power, professional ethics, and to what end knowledge may be used.

Several writers have described how mental health professionals, in part due to their socialization and social status in society, may be prone to facilitate the societal status quo by endorsing dominant social values, emphasizing individualism that minimizes sociohistorical context, and reflecting these values in the form of "value-free" scientific statements in their research and practice (61,62). For example, biological psychiatry may claim that medications correct for deficits and restore persons to what they are supposed to be (43). However, we have no clear sense of what anyone's true nature is. Answers to this question cannot be purely technical, but presumably involve values of what it means to be human in a particular society.

Social values and relationships are also embedded in our technology (63), and a social perspective allows us to recognize and assess their impact on our theories and practice. For example, if we look at neuroimaging, we see that rather than being an objective measure used in psychiatric research, magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) or the computed tomography (CT) scan must be understood as a socially constructed technique organized in the context of the academic community's decisions about what form data can take (quantitative measures) and what technology or instruments are considered acceptable (64,65). Other factors that play a role are the idea that the knowledge product can be based on interindividual differences and pooled data (so that average data may not correspond with data of any single individual in the group) and a theoretical model that assumes that abnormalities in brain structure may produce symptoms of schizophrenia or depression (64,65). It also requires an economic system that can support the cost of MRIs and CT scans.

A social perspective and quantitative research methods

An attraction of the biomedical model has been that it lends itself to more empirical (quantitative) measurements and thus mimics the physical sciences. Quantification also suggests a greater degree of predictability and control over events. Psychiatry and psychology enhance their prestige and worth by predicting and controlling aberrant human behaviors (65). When statistical significance testing is used as a basis for hypothesis testing, theories are typically "confirmed" by rejecting the null hypothesis, no matter how small or trivial the explained variance may be (65). Such computations give the impression that lawful, universal mechanisms are being uncovered. Conversely, incorporating social elements into the analysis in any substantive way begins to increase unpredictability and complexity (66,67), and, consequently, the social sphere may be cast aside as "noise" or "unexplained variance" that requires nonquantitative, or "less precise," methods for its elucidation (64).

Moreover, in using quantitative (statistical) aggregate or group data, characteristics of the "average individual" take precedence over data about distinct individuals (67). At a practical level this approach creates problems for researchers and practitioners because the fully embodied person never resembles a list of abstract traits. As Cassel (68) asserted, doctors must "ask what it is that makes a particular individual this explicit individual rather than an abstraction." Such a model omits the concrete individual, which makes it difficult to explain how psychological, biological, or social processes account for such an individual. With respect to social processes, clinicians and researchers must attend to patients' life histories, personalities, relationships, cultural backgrounds, hopes, fears, interests, and values (68). Each of these areas contributes to the course of illness and suffering because each contributes to the meaning and experience of illness (69). Thus we cannot begin to fully develop knowledge of real people's lives without their accounts of concrete, everyday experience, although it is important to avoid biographies that are ahistorical and decontexual (70).

Rather than relying on outside researchers' assumptions, researchers must consider qualitative methods such as ethnography that are oriented toward "discovering" the social world through observation and participation in natural settings. Such research can capture social processes as they develop and change and also the social meanings that generate them (71).

Conclusions

It is evident that what we mean by mind and mental disorders are intrinsically social concepts. Too frequently this simple fact has been obfuscated by psychiatry's increased reliance on the biomedical model, in which the social domain has tended to be dismissed or trivialized. This state of affairs has contributed to a variety of assumptions about the nature, course, and prevention of mental illness.

I have identified seven ways in which a social perspective can provide a complement or corrective to the prevailing assumptions of the biomedical model. They include using more sophisticated and nuanced social variables, situating research in a social context, developing new points of departure that challenge our customary ways of thinking about psychopathology, using qualitative approaches and attending to accounts of everyday experience, considering positive mental health, examining prevention from the perspective of fundamental social causes, and more explicitly recognizing the role of values in our research and practice.

Although the themes proposed here may be viewed as a reprise of the ill-fated community psychiatry movement of the 1960s, it should be recalled that the least successful aspects of the period involved theories and methods that were socially reductionistic, much as biological reductionism now vitiates some of the accomplishments of biopsychiatry. A new engagement of the social realm must avoid reductionism. At its best, the community psychiatry movement left a legacy of well-established clinical models and practices—assertive community treatment teams, psychosocial rehabilitation, partial hospitalization, supportive living, and family treatment. Bringing the social back into research and practice in a serious way will make psychiatry more relevant and scientifically robust.

Acknowledgments

The author thanks Kenneth Thompson, M.D., and Carole Lefkowitz for their assistance.

Dr. Cohen is professor and director of the division of geriatric psychiatry at the State University of New York Health Science Center at Brooklyn, Box 1203, 450 Clarkson Avenue, Brooklyn, New York 11203 (e-mail, ). Parts of this paper were presented at the annual meeting of the American Psychiatric Association held May 30 to June 4, 1998, in Toronto.

References

1. Andreasen NC: What is psychiatry? American Journal of Psychiatry 154:591-593, 1997Google Scholar

2. Kandel ER: A new intellectual framework for psychiatry. American Journal of Psychiatry 155:457-469, 1998LinkGoogle Scholar

3. Lieberman JA, Rush AJ: Redefining the role of psychiatry in medicine. American Journal of Psychiatry 153:1388-1390, 1996LinkGoogle Scholar

4. Bloom JD: Psychiatry: three models in search of a future. Psychiatric Services 47:1392-1393, 1996Google Scholar

5. Borus JF: Economics and psychiatric education: the irresistible force meets the moveable object. Harvard Review of Psychiatry 2:15-21, 1994Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

6. Detre T, McDonald MC: Managed care of the future of psychiatry. Archives of General Psychiatry 54:201-204, 1997Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

7. Shore JH: Psychiatry at a crossroad: our role in primary care. American Journal of Psychiatry 153:1398-1403, 1996LinkGoogle Scholar

8. Deetz S: The new politics of the workplace: ideology and other unobtrusive controls, in After Postmodernism: Reconstructing Ideology. Edited by Simon HW, Billig M. London, Sage, 1994Google Scholar

9. Gergen KJ: The Saturated Self. New York, Basic Books, 1991Google Scholar

10. Gergen KJ: Realties and Relationships. Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press, 1994Google Scholar

11. Pfister J, Schros N (eds): Inventing the Psychological: Toward a Cultural History of Emotional Life in America. New Haven, Conn, Yale, 1997Google Scholar

12. Moghadden FM, Studer C: Cross-cultural psychology: the frustrated gadfly's promises, potentialities, and failures, in Critical Psychology: An Introduction. Edited by Fox D, Prilleltensky I. London, Sage, 1997Google Scholar

13. Danziger K: Naming the Mind. London, Sage, 1997Google Scholar

14. Satel SL: Don't forget the addict's role in addiction. New York Times, Apr 4, 1998, p A13Google Scholar

15. Eisenberg L: The social construction of the human brain. American Journal of Psychiatry 152:1563-l575, 1995LinkGoogle Scholar

16. Kandel ER: Psychotherapy and the single synapse: the impact of psychiatric thought on neurobiologic research. New England Journal of Medicine 301:1028-1037, 1979Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

17. Post RM: Transduction of psychosocial stress into the neurobiology of recurrent affective disorder. American Journal of Psychiatry 149:999-1010, 1992LinkGoogle Scholar

18. Kellner CH, Rubinow DR, Gold PW, et al: Relationship of cortisol hypersecretion to brain CT scan alterations in depressed patients. Psychiatry Research 8:191-197 1983Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

19. Yeh SR, Fricke RA, Edwards DH: The effect of social experience on serotonergic modulation of the escape circuit of crayfish. Science 271:366-369, 1996Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

20. Gabbard GO: Mind and brain in psychiatric treatment. Bulletin of the Menninger Clinic 58:427-446, 1994MedlineGoogle Scholar

21. Lethbridge D: Mind in the World: The Marxist Psychology of Self-Actualization. Minneapolis, MEP Publications, 1992Google Scholar

22. Luria A: Towards the problem of the historical nature of psychological processes. International Journal of Psychology 6:259-272, 1971CrossrefGoogle Scholar

23. Cochrane R: The Social Creation of Mental Illness. London, Longman Group, 1983Google Scholar

24. Henderson AS: An Introduction to Social Psychiatry. Oxford, England, Oxford University Press, 1988Google Scholar

25. Klerman GL, Lavori P, Rice J, et al: Birth-cohort trends in rates of major depressive disorder among relatives of patients with affective disorder. Archives of General Psychiatry 42:689-693, 1985Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

26. Hagnell O, Lanke J, Rorsman B, et al: Are we entering an age of melancholy? Depressive illnesses in a prospective epidemiologica1 study over 25 years: the Lundby study, Sweden. Psychological Medicine 12:279-289, 1982Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

27. Ormel J, Vonkorff M, Ushul TB, et al: Common mental disorders and disability across cultures. JAMA 272:1741-1748, 1994Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

28. Al-Issa I: Cross-cultural study of symptomatology in schizophrenia. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry 13:147-156, 1968Google Scholar

29. Susser M, Watson W, Hopper K: Sociology in Medicine. New York, Oxford University Press, 1985Google Scholar

30. Sherbourne CD, Hays RD, Wells KB: Personal and psychosocial risk factors for physical and mental health outcome and course of depression among depressed patients. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 63:345-355, 1995Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

31. Meyers JK, Bean LL: A Decade Later: A Follow-up of Social Class and Mental Illness. New York, Wiley, 1968Google Scholar

32. Warner R, deGirolamo G: Schizophrenia. Geneva, World Health Organization, 1995Google Scholar

33. Gould SJ: The internal brand of the scarlet W. Natural History 107(2):22-24,70-78, 1998Google Scholar

34. Levins R, Lewontin R: The Dialectical Biologist. Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press, 1985Google Scholar

35. Tessler A: Genetic influences, in The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Social Psychology. Edited by Manstead ASR, Hewstone M. Oxford, England, Blackwell, 1996Google Scholar

36. Cohen CI, Talavera N, Hartung R: Depression among older persons with schizophrenia who live in the community. Psychiatric Services 47:601-607, 1996LinkGoogle Scholar

37. Mutaner C, Nieto FJ, O'Campo P: The bell curve: race, social class, and epidemiologic research. American Journal of Epidemiology 6:531-536, 1996CrossrefGoogle Scholar

38. Krieger N, William DR, Moss NE: Measuring social class in US public health research: concepts, methodologies, and guidelines. Annual Review of Public Health 18:341-378, 1997Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

39. Detre T: The ten commandments of psychiatric research. Biological Psychiatry 40:675-681, 1996Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

40. Kendler KS, Gardner CO: Boundaries of major depression: an evaluation of DSM-IV criteria. American Journal of Psychiatry 155:172-177, 1998AbstractGoogle Scholar

41. Kleinman A: Anthropology and psychiatry: the role of culture in cross-cultural research on illness. British Journal of Psychiatry 151:447-454, 1987Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

42. Andreasen NC: The Broken Brain: The Biological Revolution in Psychiatry. New York, Harper & Row, 1984Google Scholar

43. Franche RT: Cultures of Healing. New York, Freeman, 1995Google Scholar

44. Cohen CI, Thompson K: Homeless mentally ill or mentally ill homeless? American Journal of Psychiatry 149:816-823, 1992Google Scholar

45. Cohen CI: Poverty and the course of schizophrenia: implications for research and policy. Hospital and Community Psychiatry 44:951-958, 1993AbstractGoogle Scholar

46. Link BG, Phelan JC: Social conditions as fundamental causes of disease. Journal of Health and Social Behavior 36(special issue):80-94, 1995Google Scholar

47. Lamb HR, Zusman J: Primary prevention in perspective. American Journal of Psychiatry 136:12-17, 1979LinkGoogle Scholar

48. Cassel J: The contribution of social environment to host resistance. American Journal of Epidemiology 104:107-123, 1976Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

49. Albee GW: Toward a just society: lessons from observations on the primary prevention of psychopathology. American Psychologist 41:891-898, 1986Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

50. Link BG, Phelan JC: Understanding sociodemographic differences in health: the role of fundamental social causes (editorial). American Journal of Public Health 86:471-473, 1996Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

51. Rowe JW, Kahn RL: Human aging: usual and successful. Science 237:143-149, 1987Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

52. Castle DJ: Schizophrenia of late onset: simply a variant of early-onset disorder? Presented at the annual meeting of the American Psychiatric Association, Toronto, May 30-June 4, 1998Google Scholar

53. Seeman MV, Lang M: The role of estrogens in schizophrenia gender differences. Schizophrenia Bulletin 16:185-194, 1990Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

54. Habermas J: Theory and Practice. Boston, Beacon, 1973Google Scholar

55. Chessick RD: The application of postmodern thought to the clinical practice of psychoanalytic psychotherapy. Presented at the annual meeting of the American Academy of Psychoanalysis, New York City, May 2-5, 1996Google Scholar

56. Gergen KJ: Exploring the postmodern: perils or potentials? American Psychologist 49:412-416, 1994Google Scholar

57. Smith MB: Selfhood at risk: postmodern perils and the perils of postmodernism. American Psychologist 49:405-411, 1994CrossrefGoogle Scholar

58. Best S, Kellner D: Postmodern Theory: Critical Interrogations. New York, Guilford, 1991Google Scholar

59. Howard G: The role of values in the science of psychology. American Psychologist 40:255-265, 1985CrossrefGoogle Scholar

60. Prilleltensky I: Values, assumptions, and practices: assessing the moral implications of psychological discourse and action. American Psychologist 52:517-535, 1997Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

61. Prilleltensky I: Psychology and the status quo. American Psychologist 44:795-802, 1989CrossrefGoogle Scholar

62. Sarason SB: Psychology Misdirected. New York, Free Press, 1981Google Scholar

63. Lukacs G: History and Class Consciousness. Cambridge, Mass, MIT Press, 1971Google Scholar

64. Cohen CI: The biomedicalization of psychiatry: a critical overview. Community Mental Health Journal 29:509-521, 1993Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

65. Danziger K: Constructing the Subject: Historical Origins of Psychological Research. Cambridge, England, Cambridge University Press, 1990Google Scholar

66. Farber S: Institutional mental health and social control: the ravages of epistemological hubris. Journal of Mind and Behavior 11:285-300, 1990Google Scholar

67. Scheibe K: Mirrors, Masks, Lies, and Secrets. New York, Praeger, 1979Google Scholar

68. Cassel J: The Nature of Suffering and the Goals of Medicine. New York, Oxford University Press, 1991Google Scholar

69. Frankford DM: Scientism and econism in the regulation of health care. Journal of Health Politics, Policy, and Law 19:773-799, 1994Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

70. Hayes G: The psychology of everyday life in psychology and society, in Radical Theory and Practice. Edited by Parker I, Spears R. London, Pluto Press, 1996Google Scholar

71. Hammersley M: What's Wrong With Ethnography? London, Routledge, 1992Google Scholar