In science, a theoretical approach can broadly be viewed as belonging to a family of theories that share common
metatheoretical assumptions and commitments. By metatheoretical, we mean basic, and oftentimes implicit, tenets that relate to features of a particular theory. Indeed, the eminent philosopher-scientist Juarerro (
2023) referred to the assumptions that scientists make – when adopting a specific theoretical framework to guide their conceptualisation, planning and research designs – as ‘apparent’. These assumptions may only be ‘apparent’ because some scientists may not be fully aware of the metatheoretical commitments that accompany a particular theory. Operating at high levels of abstraction, these commitments typically frame presuppositions related to the primary subject matter addressed (see Heft,
2012). Of particular relevance to 20th -century environmental psychology are the four metatheories outlined by Altman and Rogoff (
1987): the
trait metatheory, the
interactionist metatheory, the
organismic metatheory, and the
transactional metatheory (also see Heft,
2012). It is the interactionist metatheory that is of relevance to this section, given its pervasiveness to the study of human wayfinding in psychological science (for an overview, see Heft,
2013a).
Interactionism starts from the implicit assumption that the individual is a bounded entity existing in a surround, independent to other (independently) bounded entities (Heft,
2012). In psychological science, this assumption typically manifests in three interrelated features. First, the
unit of analysis is scaled to the individual, viewed as a semi-autonomous entity that exists separate to a surround, yet is still open to ‘outside’ influences (Heft,
2001,
2012). Second, the
source of change in an individual’s organisational state resides beyond the psychological domain, either in the environment or in biological predispositions (Heft,
2001,
2012). As a brief note, a common manifestation of this second feature are information-processing models that imbue linear sequences of causation – that is, an input stimulus from the environment is processed in the mind, which leads to an outputted response by the body. Third,
causal influences are seen to operate locally and linearly, in a chain-like fashion (Heft,
2013a). Such is the pervasiveness of this ‘efficient causality’ that most 20th -century psychology conflates the word ‘cause’ with a consequent ‘effect’ (Heft,
2012, p. 15).
Interactionism and the study of human wayfinding
In an exceptional essay titled
Environment,
Cognition and Culture: Reconsidering the Cognitive Map, Heft (
2013a) demonstrates how the ripples of interactionist thinking have (implicitly and continuously) shaped studies of human wayfinding in psychological science. Such work, according to Heft, tends to orient a combination of three extant perspectives: (i) an information-processing approach (Golledge,
1987), (ii) a Piagetian developmental tradition (Hart & Moore,
1973), and iii), a nativist approach, with deep ties to Cartesian and Kantian thought (Spelke et al.,
2010). While an excursus of each is beyond the scope of this comment, it is important to note that each perspective shares at least one characteristic of interactionism. Namely, each perspective scales their unit of analysis to the individual. While directing some attention toward the environment, each conceptualises the nature of knowledge as specific to the individual, thereby epistemically separating individual processes from changes in environing conditions.
According to Dunwoody (
2006), and later advanced by Davids and Araújo (
2010), this unit of analysis is troublesome, as it perpetuates an
organismic asymmetry. In psychological science, this distortion is detected through explanations of human behaviour that inherently bias internal or representational accounts at an expense of the organism-environment
relation. Woven into the study of human wayfinding, this organismic asymmetry often leads to the view that survey knowledge and configurational understanding of the environment are critical forms of spatial knowing. It is our opinion that the target article perpetuates such an
organismic asymmetry, noted most apparently in the opening paragraph when the authors describe how humans find their way:
We need to
process spatial information from multiple sensory modalities,
maintain internal representations of the environment, plan routes, make decisions at intersections, control our gait, monitor our position and heading in space, and
orchestrate these processes by overarching executive control. (Bock et al.,
2024, p. 476, emphasis added)
While the authors do not make explicit their metatheoretical grounding, such an opening statement (to us) can be interpreted as demonstrating the specific positioning of the article as (implicitly) wedded to interactionist thinking. To elaborate: the referral to ‘
process spatial information’ clearly advocates an information-processing approach, which can be historically traced to Tolman’s (
1946,
1948) neo-behaviourist work on the cognitive map. This stance posits that individuals acquire ‘expectations’ from prior experiences, which are believed to facilitate behavioural choices and bias deliberations when faced with (unexpected) changes in an environmental layout. As the header of this section points toward, a common conceptualisation of these acquired expectations is survey knowledge about the environment, where a layout perspective is not located on the ground, but rather atop, from a drone-like, ‘birds-eye view’ (Heft,
2013a, p. 18). Second, the referral to ‘
maintain internal representations of the environment’ acknowledges a nativist approach, which has deep ties to Cartesian and Kantian thought. As Heft (
2013a, p. 18) shows, representational claims of spatial knowing speak, not to spatial relations derived from first-hand experience, but to spatial understandings that arguably
presuppose them. This perspective leads to the third point: the referral to wayfinding processes being orchestrated by ‘
overarching executive control’. Such a statement not only speaks to an ensuing body-environment and mind-body dualism, but it foregrounds the Piagetian tradition in its emphasis on presupposed mental processes believed to be in place from the outset (Heft,
2013a, p. 18).
Taking a brief step back, relevant questions to pose at this point are: Do psychological scientists interested in human movement and sports performance, need to address such metatheoretical concerns at all? In other words, why is it important to highlight the specificity of the implicated beliefs that underpin the conceptualisation chosen to frame experiments, like that of Bock et al. (
2024)? In response, it is worth noting how different metatheoretical positions oft-incorporate different conceptualisations of causality, leading to different forms of explanation (Stepp et al.,
2011). This means that our metatheoretical orientation not only (implicitly) guides subsequent empirical investigations related to a phenom of concern,
it frames the phenom of concern. Considered in the study of human wayfinding, a prevailingly interactionist orientation commits researchers to representational accounts of behaviour, as it starts from the assumption that individuals exist
separate to a surround. Thus, from the interactionist grounding Bock and colleagues (implicitly) stake out, it would appear completely sensical to investigate various cognitive strategies purported to guide wayfinding decisions at intersections, as the unit of analysis was (implicitly) scaled to the individual from the outset – or more specifically, the ‘overarching executive’ functions operating therein. Perhaps this is one of the reasons why the decision-making task used by Bock and colleagues was virtual, housed to a computer screen: i.e., because the authors implicitly follow principles of a metatheory comfortable with disembodying bounded, passive individuals in their deliberations, detaching them from the environment of which they constitute was of little concern. In this interactionist approach, there is little need to consider how the participants’ exploratory movements – nested in an environment they could actually
see,
hear,
smell,
touch and
taste – implicated how they learnt to find their way. So say the authors:
The participants were asked to follow a
prescribed route through a virtual maze that was presented on a computer screen. They were
transported passively to an intersection of corridors, where they stopped. Then they had 3000 ms to indicate whether the route continued straight on, to the left or the right, by
deflecting the handle of a joystick in the pertinent direction. They could respond anytime during the 3000-ms interval, ad [sic] were not rushed to do this quickly. (Bock et al.,
2024, p. 478, emphasis added)
To reiterate the intentions of this commentary, our concern is not to criticise the authors for their metatheoretical orientation (assumed or otherwise), nor their subsequent empirical investigation. As far as we could see, the assumptions and commitments of an interactionist metatheory were impeccably followed in their study. Rather, we simply note that wayfinding can be conceptualised from an entirely
different metatheoretical perspective: a non-representational account scaled, not to the (executive level of a) bounded individual, but to the person-environment relation. Stated differently, what if – contrary to the assertions of Bock et al. (
2024) – wayfinding is not orchestrated by ‘overarching executive’ functions, but is a process distributed across the complex, organism-environment system, facilitated by the direct perception of environmental information over time? It is thus here, where we flag our point of metatheoretical departure.