Skip to main content

PERSPECTIVE article

Front. Psychiatry, 23 December 2022
Sec. Psychopathology
This article is part of the Research Topic Emerging Treatments and Approaches for Moral Injury and Moral Distress View all 15 articles

Caught between is and ought: The Moral Dissonance Model

  • 1ARQ Centre of Expertise for the Impact of Disasters and Crisis, Diemen, Netherlands
  • 2ARQ Centre of Expertise on War, Persecution and Violence, Diemen, Netherlands

Considerable academic effort has been invested in explaining the causes of, and processes behind moral injury. These efforts are mostly focused on assessment and treatment within a clinical setting. Collective and social factors contributing to moral injury are often overlooked in current literature. This perspective article considers the role of contextual factors associated with moral injury and proposes a framework that describes their relation to individual aspects. The resulting Moral Dissonance Model (MDM) draws on existing theories and frameworks. The MDM explains how dissonance can occur when the actual behavior–the response to a morally challenging situation–contradicts with morally desirable behavior. Individual and collective factors, which change over time, contribute to the experience of dissonance. The inability to sufficiently solve dissonance can lead to moral injury, but not as a matter of course. The MDM can help to understand the underlying processes of moral distress. It raises awareness of the influence of public debate and controversy, and the resulting changing societal attitudes over time. Its implications and future use are discussed.

1. Introduction

Moral injury describes the suffering that may develop after a violation of deeply held moral beliefs and values. While consensus on the definition of moral injury is currently lacking (1), moral injury is generally assumed to result from the betrayal by a leader or trusted authority (2) or exposure to events that involve either perpetrating or witnessing actions that violate one's core beliefs (3).

The concept of moral injury is rooted in discontent with dominant theory and treatment regarding post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD). Although PTSD and moral injury show overlap in their respective symptomatology (2, 4), the moral and social dimensions of military distress were believed to be lacking in the current definition of PTSD (37). Thus, around a decade ago, military psychiatrists and psychologists adapted the concept moral injury to capture moral conflict-colored feelings of shame, guilt, betrayal and anger as a result of soldiers' deployment (5).

Most current studies on moral injury focus on its clinical assessment [e.g., (1, 811)]. As noted by Molendijk et al. (5), a consequence of such a focus is that moral injury is turned “…into an individual-focused and pathologizing construct which explains trauma only in terms of intra-psychic and inter-personal processes, and gives sufferers the status of patients with mental disorders” (p. 3). This might lead to unnecessarily pathologizing of what can be considered normal moral processes (12).

In addition, by focusing on individual suffering the role of contextual factors is easily overlooked. Given the fact that morality itself is inherently social, it is unwarranted to treat moral injury as a concept that only relates to the experience of an individual (1317). Contextual factors are all circumstances surrounding the individual's experience of an event, and include (military) culture, political mandate, and societal attitudes. These circumstances contribute to the occurrence of moral distress [e.g., (1, 5)]. For instance, Molendijk and colleagues (18, 19) describe how moral distress results from political decision-making and framing, but also from a lack of societal recognition (e.g., criticism and/or misplaced admiration regarding military missions).

In this perspective paper, we explore how to conceptualize the individual experience of moral distress in interaction with contextual factors, which can change over time. In doing so, we attempt to describe the manifestation of moral distress as a normal process, and move away from the focus on individual suffering and treatment of most current research. Building upon established theories and frameworks, we propose the Moral Dissonance Model (MDM) as a visualization of the continuous interplay between individual experience and contextual aspects. We believe that such a model is applicable to a wider context than the military, a research direction advocated by the reviews of Molendijk et al. (5) and Griffin et al. (1).

2. Establishing a comprehensive framework around is and ought

2.1. Distinguishing actual behavior from its consequences: The is

Litz et al. (3) describe a conceptualization of moral injury that is highly influential in current literature [e.g., (11)]. Their model starts with the occurrence of a “morally injurious experience”–as noted by Farnsworth et al. (14), this sometimes is even reduced to simply “moral injury.” Such terms confound the occurrence of a specific behavior (or lack thereof) with a specific outcome of that behavior (e.g., moral injury), which may “contribute to tautological assumptions about the impact of these events (e.g., that certain events necessarily cause moral injury)” [(8), p. 2]. As a first step in deconstructing moral distress, we believe it is important to steer away from such assumptions.

In the model by Litz et al. (3), transgression (i.e., the experienced dissonance between an individual's morals and their actual behavior in reaction to a morally distressing event) is the starting point of a path that leads to moral injury. This framework focusses on the individual consequences of a confrontation with a morally difficult situation and it does not take the broader surrounding context into account. Social factors–which are part of the context–are included in models such as proposed by Koenig et al. (20) and the dual process model of moral injury (21). However, these models use context primarily in relation to morally traumatized individuals within their social environment, i.e., social alienation, social anxiety and social isolation are mentioned as the consequences of traumatization (1, 21).

Models describing how people make sense of, judge, and make decisions in morally colored situations can be found outside clinical literature. These models describe the processes that influence behavior before and during a morally difficult situation, instead of focusing on its consequences. For instance, organizational pressures, moral norms and behavior expected from others are some of the factors mentioned in the Ethical Dissonance Cycle (22), the Integrated Ethical Decision-making Model (23) and the model of moral choice behavior (24).

We have applied this contextual strand of thought using the Sensemaking Intuition Model (25). Sonenshein describes how the individual, confronted with an ethical issue, constructs an instantaneous intuitive judgement, i.e., an automatic affective reaction such as “right” or “wrong.” This sensemaking is shaped by collective and individual factors; morality and ethics develop in childhood and are influenced during lifetime–especially within organizations such as the military or police where recruits are immersed in a new moral system (26, 27). Collective factors (e.g., the expectation of others and existing moral norms) also play a role in making morally challenging decisions (24).

Intuitive judgements and the resulting behavior occur rapidly and often without awareness. The actual behavior or response now constitutes the is: it cannot be altered and is (historically) situated in a certain place and time. A non-response or ‘freezing' response can be considered a reaction too; individuals feel responsible for the behavior shown even if they were unable to act in a given situation and bear no moral responsibility for harm (28, 29).

2.2. Justifying behavior: The ought

Directly following the shown behavior, the individual needs to rationalize and justify it toward him/herself and others. This happens post-hoc, and it is in this phase that dissonance can occur when the actual behavior contradicts with a morally more desirable behavior; a sense of ought. People experience dissonance as problematic and are intrinsically motivated to reduce its consequent psychological stress (30, 31).

In daily life, most of us can adequately deal with experienced dissonance. This can be partly explained by the individual's cognitive flexibility. Cognitively flexible people perceive difficult situations as controllable, are able to perceive multiple alternative explanations for life occurrences and human behavior, and are able to generate multiple alternative rationalizations to justify behavior (32, 33). Proneness to feelings of shame and neuroticism are two other aspects that may cause a higher susceptibility to experience dissonance (3). These individual factors influence the way somebody perceives and internally experiences a morally distressing event.

The distinction between what is and what ought-to-be can be traced back to 1739 when it was mentioned by Hume–albeit in a different manner (34). Hume believed it to be inherently impossible to deduce a (prescriptive) ought-statement about moral values from a (descriptive) is-statement on the state of affairs in the world. He thus separated the world of facts from the world of morality: the so-called Hume's Guillotine. While we, unlike Hume, do not purport to offer views on moral epistemology, the analogy of the is-ought problem can be made to the experience of moral dissonance. The distinction between descriptive and prescriptive cognitions has been used in the study of moral injury. Indeed, Farnsworth (35) proposed that moral injury is defined in part by prescriptive cognitions–that is, a person's judgement about what morally ought to be. For example, a veteran may feel guilt that he did not rescue a fellow soldier trapped in enemy fire and scolds himself as a coward. The veteran, in effect, prescriptively states that he should have acted differently (35).

2.3. The Moral Dissonance Model: Changes through context and time

The MDM combines the two elements described above and is depicted in Figure 1. Confronted with a morally ambiguous situation the individual intuitively tries to make sense of it before responding. This initial reaction constitutes the objective/actual behavior, or the non-alterable is. This is shown in the left of the Figure 1. After the initial response people will try to rationalize their behavior to themselves (individually) and others (socially), depicted on the right of the Figure 1. Moral dissonance arises when the displayed behavior is experienced to conflict with a morally more desirable behavior (ought), shown in the middle of the Figure 1. Simply put, an individual will think: “I should have acted otherwise”. An enduring inability to reach consonance can lead to moral injury (as depicted by the dotted line in the Figure 1).

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. The Moral Dissonance Model.

The dissonance between is and ought can become more pressing by changing moral contexts-as there is a continuous change between the displayed behavior and a present, ever-changing sense of how the individual should have acted differently. What is striking about the stories of persons who experienced morally difficult situations, is their lively recollection about the events—years, sometimes decennia, after they occurred (36). These experiences, historically situated in a certain context, such as war, are often very different from their present-day lifeworld. The is-ought dynamic is susceptible to such changes.

For one, people personally develop over time and can develop new moral values, also depending on the changing social contexts in which one lives and works. Accordingly, a person can re-alter the idea of how he or she ought to have acted in the past. Judgements by society, organizations, family, friends, or bystanders can also upset an earlier felt balance (18). In certain moral contexts expectations prevail that allow or even encourage actions that are vehemently rejected in other contexts. For instance, there can be a stark difference between the circumstances and moral values of the workplace and those in the private sphere; the use of violence in the military is seen as morally acceptable and can conflict with privately held values. After acting out (violently) in concurrence with military values, privately a person can think that he or she ought to have acted differently, causing dissonance.

Contexts change not only over place but also over time, for example when a service member returns home after deployment of several months. During their reintegration into society, unwarranted admiration for veterans, or, conversely, public criticism on a military mission can result in the experience of misrecognition and may cause moral injury (18). The moral world of the military mission wherein a service member acted in a certain manner, then collides with the moral world of society.

As an illustration of how a change of context can influence the individual's perception of a morally difficult situation, we describe the experience of a Dutch veteran stationed in Afghanistan1. As part of the International Assistance Security Forces (ISAF), the veteran regularly had to visit with an Afghan police commander, as he was an important actor in local security and in the ISAF network. This commander was accompanied by a so-called “chaiboy,” a 10-year-old boy who danced and poured tea for the guests. It was known that the commander also sexually abused the child. The veteran explained how at the time, the situation caused dissonance: despite feeling extremely uncomfortable, the veteran chose not to intervene. She knew that it was impossible—as a woman and a foreigner—to confront the commander. It would ruin the relationship.

Her rationalization was sufficient in the context of the mission in Afghanistan. Upon return to the Netherlands, however, following the pregnancy with her first child, doubts did arise. With the birth of her daughter, she realized how vulnerable children are. Many years later, through individual change and a change of context, she felt powerless–an emotion she could not allow before. It was impossible to change the outcome of the Afghanistan dilemma, she did however look for positive changes she could make in her everyday life, by speaking out against discrimination or sexual intimidation, and by deciding, three weeks after the birth of her first daughter, to have her second daughter adopted.

3. Discussion

This perspective paper addresses the issue that current moral injury literature is overly focused on a clinical construction of the concept–where, in fact, moral injury has roots in, and implications for, both individual experiences and the social fabric itself (17). We introduced the Moral Dissonance Model (MDM) as a conceptual framework which can help understand the interplay of individual and collective factors related to moral injury beyond the clinical setting. Although the MDM relates to the influential causal framework of Litz et al. (3), the latter model specifically aims to reconstruct a process that leads to moral injury. The MDM, on the other hand, takes an opposite approach: dissonance, which can occur in everyday situations, is a normal human reaction that will not necessarily end in “injury”–but still can be tremendously distressing (37, 38).

In constructing the MDM, we shy away from the more clinical reasoning about moral injury. As noted by Griffin et al. [(1), p. 357], moral distress “… is a product of culturally imbued, shared values that are internalized by individuals—some of which (e.g., loyalty to country) may conflict with others (e.g., thou shalt not kill).” Even if moral injury occurs, it is not solely a product of intrapsychic conflict, and recovery is intrinsically connected with the extent personal views are shared with others. The context (be it family, community, working organization or culture) is part of the healing process in which the individual must return (p. 358). Such a general process of dissonance is also applicable to work sectors outside the military domain, which often is a focus in moral injury research (2, 39). During the recent COVID-19 pandemic, it was obvious how much medical professionals were confronted with moral dilemmas (40, 41). Indeed, the term moral distress relates to the nursing profession (42) and implies the experience of knowing the right thing to do while being in a situation in which it is nearly impossible to do so.

We believe the MDM can help understand the underlying processes of moral distress and put them into words–it raises awareness of the influence of public debate and controversy, and the resulting changing societal attitudes over time. However, we do recognize the MDM has limitations. A generalized model does no justice to the complex reality people in moral ambiguous situations are confronted with. Our example of the Dutch veteran stationed in Afghanistan is a case in point: she experienced dissonance from the outset and this was not completely resolved with her post-hoc rationalization. Dissonance caused by a moral violation, even before the actor has shown any behavior, is not explained by the MDM. Also, the MDM does not explain consequences as described by McDonald (43), who holds that moral injury does not only concern one's sense of moral failing, but also the painful thought that moral structure does not exist in the world at all.

In “normalizing” the moral dissonance process, also new questions emerge. In what way differs immediate dissonance caused by a perceived moral violation (as described in the example of the Dutch veteran), from behavior-based dissonance (as described in the MDM)? How do persons experience moral dissonance and how can we provide solutions to alleviate dissonance caused by an is-ought problem? How often does moral dissonance lead to moral injury and what are protective factors in the process from dissonance to injury? In understanding the factors that induce dissonance, are we able to prevent it? And last but not least: what interventions at a contextual level can help counter individually felt moral distress?

Of course, there are cases in which the moral dissonance is so severe that it causes issues that can be labeled as moral injury. For these cases, treatment is needed. In therapy the patient can share the experience of a morally complex situation and the resulting feelings of shame and guilt. One form of treatment that shows a connection to the MDM is Acceptance and Commitment Therapy [ACT, (12)], which instructs the patient on the informative qualities of the moral pain. We believe the MDM can be part of the informative procedure, as it helps to define a certain type of moral dissonance and provides an easily comprehendible concept (is-ought).

In conclusion, a broader scope on what constitutes moral distress is needed to fully grasp all its influences. But even if we focus on the clinical diagnosis of moral injury, it should be recognized that it is not limited to repairing the wounds of the individual. In the end, military personnel, but also first responders and healthcare professionals are doing their work for the sake and benefit of society. Therefore, civilians should learn from and listen to their experiences of morally demanding situations (17) considering the complex and sometimes gruesome reality of these stories. Moral injury is not only a burden on the morally wounded themselves, but a matter that concerns us all.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Author contributions

HT and BN: conception, writing, and research. All authors contributed to the article and approved the submitted version.

Funding

The fees of this publication are funded by ARQ Centre of Expertise for the Impact of Disasters and Crisis and ARQ Centre of Excellence on War, Persecution and Violence.

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Ilse Raaijmakers PhD, Jackie June ter Heide PhD MPhil for their commentary earlier drafts of this article, and Arjen van Lil MA for editorial notes.

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher's note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Footnotes

1. ^In 2019, this veteran was interviewed for a related research project that explored moral dilemmas within several professions, including military, police, prosecution, health care, and humanitarian aid work (36).

References

1. Griffin BJ, Purcell N, Burkman K, Litz BT, Bryan CJ, Schmitz M, et al. Moral injury: an integrative review. J Trauma Stress. (2019) 32:350–62. doi: 10.1002/jts.22362

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

2. Shay J. Moral injury. Psychoanal Psychol. (2014) 31:182–91. doi: 10.1037/a0036090

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

3. Litz BT, Stein N, Delaney E, Lebowitz L, Nash WP, Silva C, et al. Moral injury and moral repair in war veterans: a preliminary model and intervention strategy. Clin Psychol Rev. (2009) 29:695–706. doi: 10.1016/j.cpr.2009.07.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

4. Maguen S, Litz BT. Moral injury in veterans of war. PTSD Res Q. (2012) 23:1–6.

Google Scholar

5. Molendijk T, Verkoren W, Drogendijk A, Elands M, Kramer EH, Smit A, et al. Contextual dimensions of moral injury: an interdisciplinary review. Mil Psychol. (2022) 1–12. doi: 10.1080/08995605.2022.2035643

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

6. DePrince AP, Freyd JJ. The harm of trauma: pathological fear, shattered assumptions, or betrayal. In Kauffman J, editor. Loss of the Assumptive World: A Theory of Traumatic Loss. Brunner-Routledge (2002). p. 71–82.

Google Scholar

7. Drescher KD, Foy DW, Kelly C, Leshner A, Schutz K, Litz B. An exploration of the viability and usefulness of the construct of moral injury in war veterans. Traumatology. (2011) 17:8–13. doi: 10.1177/1534765610395615

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

8. Frankfurt S, Frazier F. A review of research on moral injury in combat veterans. Mil Psychol. (2016) 28:318–30. doi: 10.1037/mil0000132

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

9. Jinkerson JD. Defining and assessing moral injury: a syndrome perspective. Traumatology. (2016) 22:122–30. doi: 10.1037/trm0000069

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

10. Yeterian JD, Berke DS, Carney JR, McIntyre-Smith A, St Cyr K, King L, et al. Defining and measuring moral injury: rationale, design, and preliminary findings from the moral injury outcome scale consortium. J Traum Stress. (2019) 32:363–72. doi: 10.1002/jts.22380

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

11. Mensink B, van Schagen A, van der Aa N, Ter Heide F. Moral injury in trauma-exposed, treatment-seeking police officers and military veterans: latent class analysis. Front Psychiatry. (2022) 13:904659. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2022.904659

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

12. Farnsworth JK, Drescher KD, Evans WR, Walser RD. A functional approach to understanding and treating military-related moral injury. J Contextual Behav Sci. (2017) 6:391–7. doi: 10.1016/j.jcbs.2017.07.003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

13. Berger P, Luckman T. The Social Construction of Reality. A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. London: The Penguin Press (1967).

Google Scholar

14. Farnsworth JK Drescher KD Nieuwsma JA Walser RB and Currier JM. The role of moral emotions in military trauma: implications for the study and treatment of moral injury. Rev Gen Psychol. (2014) 18:249–62. doi: 10.1037/gpr0000018

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

15. Gert B, Gert J. The Definition of Morality. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (2020). Available online at: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/morality-definition (accessed October 01, 2022).

Google Scholar

16. Haidt J. Morality. Perspect Psychol Sci. (2008) 3:65–72. doi: 10.1111/j.1745-6916.2008.00063.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

17. Buechner BD. Untold stories of moral injury: what we are learning—and not learning—from military veterans in transition. Front Commun. (2020) 5:599301. doi: 10.3389/fcomm.2020.599301

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

18. Molendijk T. Moral injury in relation to public debates: the role of societal misrecognition in moral conflict-colored trauma among soldiers. Soc Sci Med. (2018) 211:314–20. doi: 10.1016/j.socscimed.2018.06.042

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

19. Molendijk T. The role of political practices in moral injury: a study of Afghanistan veterans. Polit Psychol. (2019) 40:261–75. doi: 10.1111/pops.12503

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

20. Koenig HG, Ames D, Youssef NA, Oliver JP, Volk F, Teng EJ, et al. The moral injury symptom scale-military version. J Relig Health. (2018) 57:249–65. doi: 10.1007/s10943-017-0531-9

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

21. Barr N, Atuel H, Saba S, Castro CA. Toward a dual process model of moral injury and traumatic illness Front Psychiatry. (2022) 1898:1–12. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2022.883338

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

22. Burchard M. Ethical dissonance and response to destructive leadership: a proposed model. Emerg Leadership J. (2011) 4:154–76.

Google Scholar

23. Schwartz MS. Ethical decision-making theory: an integrated approach. J. Business Ethics. (2016) 139:755–76. doi: 10.1007/s10551-015-2886-8

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

24. Chorus CG. Models of moral decision making: literature review and research agenda for discrete choice analysis. J Choice Model. (2015) 16:69–85. doi: 10.1016/j.jocm.2015.08.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

25. Sonenshein S. The role of construction, intuition, and justification in responding to ethical issues at work: the sensemaking-intuition model. Acad Manage Rev. (2007) 32:1022–40. doi: 10.5465/amr.2007.26585677

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

26. Keltner D, Haidt J, Shiota MN. (2006). Social functionalism and the evolution of emotions. In:Schaller M, Simpson JA, Kenrick DT, , editors. Evolution and Social Psychology. New York, NY: Psychology Press. p. 115–42.

Google Scholar

27. Van Baarda T, Verweij D. Militaire Ethiek Een algemene inleiding. In: Van Baarda T, Verweij D. Militaire Ethiek. Ethiek en integriteit bij de krijgsmacht, morele vorming en dilemmatraining. Budel: Uitgeverij Damon (2010). p. 17–34.

Google Scholar

28. Cavalera C. COVID-19 Psychological implications: the role of shame and guilt. Front Psychol. (2020) 11:571828. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.571828

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

29. Zimmerman MJ. An Essay on Moral Responsibility, Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield (1988).

Google Scholar

30. Egan LC, Santos LR, Bloom P. The origins of cognitive dissonance: evidence from children and monkeys. Psychol Sci. (2007) 18:978–83. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.02012.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

31. Metin I, Camgoz SM. The advances in the history of cognitive dissonance theory. Int J Human Soc Sci. (2011) 1:131–6.

Google Scholar

32. Dennis JP, Vander Wal JS. The cognitive flexibility inventory: instrument development and estimates of reliability and validity. Cogn Ther Res. (2010) 34:241–53. doi: 10.1007/s10608-009-9276-4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

33. Robinson A. The Impact of Cognitive Dissonance and Cognitive Flexibility on Belief Systems [research paper]. Minnetonka: Adler graduate school (2013).

Google Scholar

34. Hume D. Treatise of Human Nature. (1739). Available online at: https://gutenberg.org/ebooks/4705 (accessed February 21, 2022).

Google Scholar

35. Farnsworth JK. Is and ought: descriptive and prescriptive cognitions in military-related moral injury. J Trauma Stress. (2019) 32:373–81. doi: 10.1002/jts.22356

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

36. Nauta B, Te Brake H, Raaijmakers I. Dat ene dilemma: Persoonlijke verhalen over morele keuzes op de werkvloer. [That one dilemma: personal stories about moral choices in the workplace] Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press (2019).

Google Scholar

37. Festinger L. A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press (1957).

Google Scholar

38. Barkan R, Ayal S, Ariely D. Ethical dissonance, justifications, and moral behavior. Curr Opin Psychol. (2015) 6:1571161. doi: 10.1016/j.copsyc.2015.08.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

39. Currier JM, Holland JM, Drescher K, Foy D. Initial psychometric evaluation of the moral injury questionnaire–military version. Clin Psychol Psychother. (2015) 22:54–63. doi: 10.1002/cpp.1866

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

40. Borges LM, Barnes SM, Farnsworth JK, Bahraini NH, Brenner LA. A commentary on moral injury among health care providers during the COVID-19 pandemic. Psychol Trauma. (2020) 12:S138–40. doi: 10.1037/tra0000698

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

41. Cartolovni A, Stolt M, Scott PA, Suhonen R. Moral injury in healthcare professionals: a scoping review and discussion. Nurs Ethics. (2021) 28:590–602. doi: 10.1177/0969733020966776

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

42. Jameton A. Nursing Practice, the Ethical Issues. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall (1984).

Google Scholar

43. McDonald M. Haunted by a different ghost: Re-thinking moral injury. Ess Philos. (2017) 18:1–16. doi: 10.7710/1526-0569.1581

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: moral injury, moral dissonance, decision-making, moral distress, military, social context, modeling, framework

Citation: Te Brake H and Nauta B (2022) Caught between is and ought: The Moral Dissonance Model. Front. Psychiatry 13:906231. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2022.906231

Received: 28 March 2022; Accepted: 05 December 2022;
Published: 23 December 2022.

Edited by:

Chelsea Jones, University of Alberta, Canada

Reviewed by:

Erin Sugrue, Augsburg University, United States
Sara Rodrigues, CoE on PTSD, Canada

Copyright © 2022 Te Brake and Nauta. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Hans Te Brake, yes h.te.brake@impact.arq.org

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.