Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Hum. Neurosci., 08 December 2017
Sec. Cognitive Neuroscience
Volume 11 - 2017 | https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2017.00602

Commentary: What Is Art Good For? The Socio-Epistemic Value of Art

  • 1Danish Research Centre for Magnetic Resonance, Copenhagen University Hospital, Copenhagen, Denmark
  • 2Center for Decision Neuroscience, Copenhagen Business School, Frederiksberg, Denmark
  • 3Human Evolution and Cognition Group (EvoCog), University of the Balearic Islands and IFISC, Palma de Mallorca, Spain

A commentary on
What Is Art Good For? The Socio-Epistemic Value of Art

by Sherman, A., and Morrissey, C. (2017). Front. Hum. Neurosci. 11:411. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2017.00411

Art, in fact, can be nothing but violence, cruelty, and injustice.

—Marinetti, I manifesti del Futurismo

Does neuroaesthetics have a problem? Sherman and Morrissey (2017) criticize the field for focusing narrowly on how art elicits pleasurable responses, and for neglecting its social relevance and impact. Neuroaesthetics, they argue, reduces the experience of art to isolated individuals' ratings in artificial lab settings, and ignores “socially-relevant outcomes of art appreciation or the social context of art creation and art appreciation.” Consequently, it fails to “capture or appreciate the social, cultural, or historical situatedness of the art-object or the person whose experience is being studied.”

There is no question that we know little about the social aspect of art behavior and its underlying psychological and neurobiological mechanisms. Because art is often a transient phenomenon created as function of a social act, as in music, dance, or performance, the features of collective settings surely modulate cognition and affect. Dance, for instance, can coordinate emotional responses to promote social cohesion (Vicary et al., 2017). Nevertheless, the precise way in which social settings influence brain activity when experiencing art remains largely unknown.

We know of no neuroaestetician who would not welcome research on the psychology and biology of art behavior in social contexts. Yet, Sherman and Morrissey (2017) portray neuroaesthetics as dismissing such research topics and promoting an a-social conception of art experience. They fault neuroaesthetics for “conflating the art with aesthetics,” for having “privileged investigating individual judgments of beauty or preference,” for construing art appreciation as a “passive reception of perceptual information from art-objects,” and for discounting “what many would consider the very essence of art: its communicative nature, its capacity to encourage personal growth (…), to challenge preconceptions (…), and to provide clarity on ambiguous concepts or ideas.”

This is a misrepresentation of neuroaesthetics. We have refuted these and other similar contentions extensively elsewhere (Pearce et al., 2016). Here we only have space to make three points. First, although many neuroaesthetics studies do aim to understand how the brain constructs aesthetic value, it is hardly the only aspect of art experience being investigated. Much psychological and neuroscientific research on art actually concerns perception and representation, not valuation (e.g., Bromberger et al., 2011; Pegors et al., 2015; Choo et al., 2017). Second, neuroaesthetics does not discount the social dimension of art experience. Music research, for instance, has uncovered that people compute tones using expectations set by music's tonal system and internalized as members of a social community (Brattico and Pearce, 2013; Egermann et al., 2013). Third, contrary to Sherman and Morrissey's (2017) claims, researchers have adapted their experimental paradigms to social art contexts, including museums, concert halls, and theaters (e.g., Tschacher et al., 2012; Egermann et al., 2013; Jola and Grosbras, 2013; Brieber et al., 2014; Vicary et al., 2017).

These and other ongoing studies prove that the factor limiting scientific research of art in its social milieu is not one of principle, but one of technological availability. Technology (e.g., eye trackers, physiological monitoring) is becoming cheaper and increasingly portable, enabling the study of art in its social context. Behind this misleading picture of neuroaesthetics we detect another, perhaps the true, goal of Sherman and Morrisey's paper: to defend a specific conception of what art is—or should be. At the heart of their criticism lurks an assumption: that art is a force for good—for social good, moral good. Sherman and Morrisey presume that art can make us better people: “engaging with art can be potentially transformative, for it encourages us to consider the welfare and good of other people.”

It is this assumption that explains the peculiar choice of purported social functions they urge neuroaesthetics to study: to enhance self-understanding and to enhance the understanding of others. But Sherman and Morrissey's (2017) claim rests only on their own intuition, not on empirical evidence showing that art actually does improve us as moral beings. They are upfront about this fact, basing their case for both proposed functions of art solely on philosophical authority. An empirical science of art, however, cannot be motivated solely by armchair assumptions about the nature of art. Philosophy and art history abound with views contrary to the notion that art is a force for social good. Plato vilified art for being unable to produce true ideas, and for emotionally enticing and contaminating the innocent minds of Athens's youth. Innumerable thinkers, parents, and rulers, in the wake of Plato, have viewed art more as a force of social evil than of social good. Can we base a proper empirical science of human art experience on whatever intuitions and assumptions we find most appealing?

Art has come to occupy a problematic place in psychology and neuroscience. Several recent papers have seen fit to propose behavioral, cognitive and emotional traits/processes as integral to art experience. However, such proposals are largely unconstrained by knowledge about cognition and neuroscience, and rarely backed up by evidence (e.g., Bullot and Reber, 2013; Christensen, 2017; Menninghaus et al., 2017; Pelowski et al., 2017). As an object of research, art is so broad and imbued with centuries of philosophical speculation that any claim seems to have an aura of validity. Art appears to be good-for everything: it can be imputed with whatever feature or function strikes a researcher's fancy. Whether such feature or function is supported by empirical evidence, or is in accordance with current knowledge about human brain and cognition, seems only a secondary concern. To advance as a scientific discipline, neuroasthetics must do better.

Author Contributions

All authors listed have made a substantial, direct, and intellectual contribution to the work, and approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

References

Brattico, E., and Pearce, M. T. (2013). The neuroaesthetics of music. Psychol. Aesthetics Creativity Arts 7, 48–61. doi: 10.1037/a0031624

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brieber, D., Nadal, M., Leder, H., and Rosenberg, R. (2014). Art in time and space: Context modulates the relation between art experience and viewing time. PLoS ONE 9:e99019. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0099019

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bromberger, B., Sternschein, R., Widick, P., Smith, I. I. W., and Chatterjee, A. (2011). The right hemisphere in esthetic perception. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 5:109. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2011.00109

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bullot, N. J., and Reber, R. (2013). The artful mind meets art history: toward a psycho-historical framework for the science of art appreciation. Behav. Brain Sci. 36, 123–137. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X12000489

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Choo, H., Nasar, J. L., Nikrahei, B., and Walther, D. B. (2017). Neural codes of seeing architectural styles. Sci. Rep. 7:40201. doi: 10.1038/srep40201

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Christensen, J. F. (2017). Pleasure junkies all around! Why it matters and why ‘the arts’ might be the answer: a biopsychological perspective. Proc. Biol. Sci. 284:20162837. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2016.2837

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Egermann, H., Pearce, M. T., Wiggins, G. A., and McAdams. (2013). Probabilistic models of expectation violation predict psychophysiological emotional responses to live concert music. Cogn. Affect. Behav. Neurosci. 13, 533–553. doi: 10.3758/s13415-013-0161-y

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jola, C., and Grosbras, M. H. (2013). In the here and now: enhanced motor corticospinal excitability in novices when watching live compared to video recorded dance. Cogn. Neurosci. 4, 90–98. doi: 10.1080/17588928.2013.776035

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Menninghaus, W., Wagner, V., Hanich, J., Wassiliwizky, E., Jacobsen, T., and Koelsch, S. (2017). The Distancing–Embracing model of the enjoyment of negative emotions in art reception. Behav. Brain Sci. 40:e347. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X17000309

CrossRef Full Text

Pearce, M. T., Zaidel, D. W., Vartanian, O., Skov, M., Leder, H., Chatterjee, A., et al. (2016). Neuroaesthetics: the cognitive neuroscience of aesthetic experience. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 11, 265–279. doi: 10.1177/1745691615621274

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pegors, T. K., Kable, J. W., Chatterjee, A., and Epstein, R. A. (2015). Common and unique representations in pFC for face and place attractiveness. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 27, 959–973. doi: 10.1162/jocn_a_00777

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pelowski, M., Markey, P. S., Forster, M., Gerger, G., and Leder, H. (2017). Move me, astonish me… delight my eyes and brain: the Vienna Integrated Model of top-down and bottom-up processes in Art Perception (VIMAP) and corresponding affective, evaluative, and neurophysiological correlates. Phys. Life Rev. 21, 80–125. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2017.02.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sherman, A., and Morrissey, C. (2017). What is art good for? the socio-epistemic value of art. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 11:411. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2017.00411

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tschacher, W., Greenwood, S., Kirchberg, V., Wintzerith, S., van den Berg, K., and Tröndle, M. (2012). Physiological correlates of aesthetic perception of artworks in a museum. Psychol. Aesthetics Creativity Arts 6, 96–103. doi: 10.1037/a0023845

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vicary, S., Sperling, M., von Zimmermann, J., Richardson, D. C., and Orgs, G. (2017). Joint action aesthetics. PLoS ONE 12:e0180101. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0180101

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: neuroaesthetics, empirical aesthetics, art, cognitive neuroscience, social neuroscience

Citation: Skov M and Nadal M (2017) Commentary: What Is Art Good For? The Socio-Epistemic Value of Art. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 11:602. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2017.00602

Received: 25 September 2017; Accepted: 27 November 2017;
Published: 08 December 2017.

Edited by:

Arthur M. Jacobs, Freie Universität Berlin, Germany

Reviewed by:

Massimiliano Palmiero, University of L'Aquila, Italy

Copyright © 2017 Skov and Nadal. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Martin Skov, martins@drcmr.dk

Download