Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-8mjnm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T11:11:02.970Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Thomas S. Kuhn*
Affiliation:
Massachusetts Institute of Technology

Extract

Twenty years have passed since Paul Feyerabend and I first used in print a term we had borrowed from mathematics to describe the relaationship between successive scientific theories. ‘Incommensurability’ was the term; each of us was led to it by problems we had encountered in interpreting scientific texts (Feyerabend 1962; Kuhn 1962). My use of the term was broader than his; his claims for the phenomenon were more sweeping than mine; but our overlap at that time was substantial. Each of us was centrally concerned to show that the meanings of scientific terms and concepts — ‘force’ and ‘mass’, for example, or ‘element’ and ‘compound’ — often changed with the theory in which they were deployed. And each of us claimed that when such changes occurred, it was impossible to define all the terms of one theory in the vocabulary of the other.

Type
Part XVI. Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability
Copyright
Copyright © 1983 Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

Since this paper was first drafted, many people have contributed to its improvement, among them colleagues at M.I.T. and auditors at the P.S.A. meeting and at the Columbia seminar in History and Philosophy of Science where a preliminary version was first tried out. I am grateful to all of them, above all to Ned Block, Paul Horwich, Nathaniel Kuhn, Stephen Stich, and my two official commentators.

References

Apel, Karl-Otto. (1972). “The A Priori of Communication and the Foundation of the Humanities.” Man and World 5: 3-37. (As reprinted in Dallmayr and McCarthy (1977). Pages 292-315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dallmayr, F.A., and McCarthy, T.A. (eds.). (1977). Understanding and Social Inquiry. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. (1974). “The Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme.” Proceedings & Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 47: 5-20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, P.K. (1962). “Explanation, Reduction, and Empiricism.” In Scientific Explanation, Space, and Time. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume III.) Edited by Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G.. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Pages 28-97.Google Scholar
Hanson, N.R. (1958). Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip. (1978). “Theories, Theorists, and Theoretical Change.” Philosophical Review 87: 519-547.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1964). “A Function for Thought Experiments.” In Mélanges Alexandre Koyré, Volume I. Edited by Cohen, I.B. and Taton, R.. Paris: Hermann. Pages 307-334. (As reprinted in Kuhn (1977). Pages 240-265.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1974). “Second Thoughts on Paradigms.” In The Structure of Soientific Theories. Edited by Suppe, F.. Urbana: University of Illinois Press. Pages 459-482. (As reprinted in Kuhn (1977). Pages 293-319.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1977). The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. (1970). “How to Define Theoretical Terms.” Journal of Philosophy 67: 427-446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. (1972). “Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50: 249-258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary, (1981). Reason. Truth and History. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W.V.O. (1960). Word and Object. New York: Technology Press and John Wiley.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Israel. (1967). Science and Subjectivity. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Shapere, Dudley. (1966). “Meaning and Scientific Change.” In Mind and Cosmos: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy. (University of Pittsburgh Series in the Philosophy of Science, Volume III.) Edited by Colodny, R.G.. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. Pages 1(1-85).Google Scholar
Sneed, J.D. (1971). The Logical Structure of Mathematical Physics. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stegmüller, Wolfgang. (1973). Theorienstrukturen und Theoriendynamik (This is Volume 2 pt. 2 of Stegmüller's Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und analytischen Philosophy.) Berlin: Springer-Verlag. (As reprinted as The Structure and Dynamics of Theories. (trans.) Wohlhueter, W.. New York: Springer-Verlag, 1976.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. (1971). “Interpretation and the Sciences of Man.” Review of Metaphysics 25: 3-51. (As reprinted in Dallmayr and McCarthy (1977). Pages 101-131.)Google Scholar