Review
Experimental Pragmatics: a Gricean turn in the study of language

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2008.07.009Get rights and content

Discerning the meaning of an utterance requires not only mastering grammar and knowing the meanings of words but also understanding the communicative (i.e. pragmatic) features of language. Although it has been an ever present aspect of linguistic analyses and discussions, it is only over the last ten years or so that cognitive scientists have been investigating – in a concerted fashion – the pragmatic features of language experimentally. We begin by highlighting Paul Grice’s contributions to ordinary language philosophy and show how it has led to this active area of experimental investigation. We then focus on two exemplary phenomena – ‘scalar inference’ and ‘reference resolution’ – before considering other topics that fit into the paradigm known as ‘experimental pragmatics’.

Section snippets

What does ‘mean’ mean?

Grice’s [2] initial contribution was to propose a novel analysis of meaning. He distinguished ‘sentence meaning’ (the semantic properties of a sentence assigned to it by the grammar) and ‘speaker’s meaning’ (what the speaker actually intended to communicate by uttering a sentence). Retrieving a sentence meaning from an actual utterance is a matter of decoding that sentence, that is, of discovering the semantic properties that the grammar pairs to its acoustic form. Retrieving the speaker’s

Scales and Inference

John Stuart Mill noted (as cited in Ref. [8]), that utterances such as ‘I saw some of your children today’ are often interpreted as ‘I didn’t see all of your children today’ because if the speaker meant the more informative ‘all’, he would have said so. Although intuitive, this interpretation raises an inconsistency because the semantic meaning of ‘some’ is, in fact, compatible with ‘all’. (To appreciate this, consider a teacher who coyly tells her students ‘some of you passed the exam’ when in

Definite Reference

In referring to an object, interpretation is usually semantically underdetermined. For example, when an interlocutor says ‘I used to work for that paper’ (while pointing to the latest edition of a newspaper), the addressee’s interpretation relies heavily on identifying the speaker’s intention. ‘Reference’ is, thus, another natural area of utterance interpretation that fits into a Gricean framework and one that has inspired much experimental work. One constraint advanced to determine the

What is at stake?

Taken together, these two phenomena reveal what factors are in play when discussing utterance interpretation, which are ‘code’ (the words used), the (non-demonstrative) inferences they engender in context and a role for intentions (theory of mind). In the case of scalars, the theoretical tension has focused on the relative importance of code and inference, in which some researchers aim to include narrowing into the code (e.g. by making the distinction based on downward entailment) and others

Acknowledgements

We thank Dan Sperber, Edmundo Kronmuller and three anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments.

References (52)

  • B. Keysar

    Limits on theory of mind use in adults

    Cognition

    (2003)
  • B. Keysar

    Definite reference and mutual knowledge: process models of common ground in comprehension

    J. Mem. Lang.

    (1998)
  • J.E. Hanna

    The effects of common ground and perspective on domains of referential interpretation

    J. Mem. Lang.

    (2003)
  • J.P. Laurent

    On understanding idiomatic language: the salience hypothesis assessed by ERP’s

    Brain Res.

    (2006)
  • H. Clark

    Responding to indirect speech acts

    Cognit. Psychol.

    (1979)
  • R. Gibbs et al.

    Striving for optimal relevance when answering questions

    Cognition

    (2008)
  • E. Kronmüller et al.

    Perspective-free pragmatics: broken precedents and the recovery-from-preemption hypothesis

    J. Mem. Lang.

    (2007)
  • I.A. Noveck et al.

    Experimental Pragmatics

    (2004)
  • P. Grice

    Studies in the Way of Words

    (1989)
  • B.P. Ackerman

    Contextual integration and utterance interpretation: the ability of children and adults to interpret sarcastic utterances

    Child Dev.

    (1982)
  • N. Schwarz

    Cognition and Communication: Judgmental Biases, Research Methods and the Logic of Conversation

    (1996)
  • A. Tversky et al.

    Extension versus intuitive reasoning: the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment

    Psychol. Rev.

    (1983)
  • G. Politzer et al.

    Are conjunction rule violations the result of conversational rule violations?

    J. Psycholinguist. Res.

    (1991)
  • L. Horn

    Implicature

  • S. Levinson

    Presumptive Meanings

    (2000)
  • G. Chierchia

    Scalar implicatures, polarity phenomena, and the syntax/pragmatics interface

  • Cited by (145)

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text