Elsevier

Journal of Mathematical Psychology

Volume 47, Issues 5–6, October–December 2003, Pages 557-567
Journal of Mathematical Psychology

Deriving quality-adjusted life years (QALYs) from constant proportional time tradeoff and risk posture conditions

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jmp.2003.09.001Get rights and content

Abstract

With foundations in decision theory, Quality-Adjusted Life Years (QALYs) are the most important measure of health outcome in medical decision making. Constant proportional time tradeoff (CP-TTO) is a condition on riskless value with empirical support in the QALY literature. The primary use of CP-TTO in previous axiomatizations of QALYs has been to guarantee that the utility of health state and survival duration is a power function of duration. We show that CP-TTO has other useful applications in QALY research. Under mild conditions CP-TTO implies an additive value function. Furthermore, CP-TTO can be combined with assumptions of risky utility to yield several different parametric QALY representations, including one that is inconsistent with utility independence. We find that CP-TTO simplifies axiomatizations of QALY representations in the sense that if CP-TTO is among the assumptions of a QALY axiomatization, other standard preference assumptions, e.g., double cancellation or utility independence, become redundant and can be dropped from the axiom system. This can be desirable if it allows one to drop from the axiomatization an assumption that is practically difficult to test, e.g., double cancellation.

Introduction

Suppose a patient tells you that she is indifferent between living 40 years in poor health and living 20 years in full health. If she is also indifferent between living 30 years in poor health and 15 years in full health, then she has exhibited behavior consistent with the assumption of constant proportional time tradeoff. More generally, under constant proportional time tradeoff (CP-TTO), if for some health states a and b, we find axby is an indifference expressed by the patient between living x years in a health state a and y years in a health state b, then for all c>0, such that cx,cyM, a[cx]∼b[cy].

Under mild conditions, CP-TTO implies the necessary assumptions for additive conjoint measurement and a multiplicative representation of riskless value. Because risky utility represents the same preferences over outcomes as riskless value, risky utility is a strictly increasing function of riskless value (Keeney & Raiffa, 1993). This fact will allow us to identify several useful characteristics of utility functions for which we know that preferences satisfy CP-TTO. Following a similar argument to that of Maas and Wakker (1994), we show that CP-TTO together with a few assumptions of risky choice imply specific parametric forms of the utility of duration, including in one case a model that is inconsistent with utility independence. We also find that CP-TTO simplifies axiomatizations of quality-adjusted life years (QALY) representations in the sense that if CP-TTO is among the assumptions of a QALY axiomatization, other standard preference assumptions, e.g., double cancellation or utility independence, become redundant and can be dropped from the axiom system. This line of argument is similar in spirit, if not in the formal details, to arguments in Wakker (1989), Ebert (1988), and Miyamoto and Wakker (1996).

It is well known that under CP-TTO, when utility independence is invoked, the utility function is a member of the log/power family. Characterizing the utility of survival duration reduces in this case to the problem of estimating a single risk parameter (Pliskin, Shepard, & Weinstein, 1980). We show that invoking constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) along with CP-TTO also implies a log/power utility function. Thus, CRRA and utility independence imply each other when CP-TTO is invoked (This equivalence occurs when the health domain satisfies a restricted solvability condition. When restricted solvability is not assumed, CRRA appears to be a stronger condition than utility independence (see Theorem 4.1)). When constant absolute risk aversion (CARA) is then added, the utility function becomes linear and the riskless value function represents risky choices as well. In another line of development, we show that the utility function is an exponentiated linear model when CARA and CP-TTO are assumed and utility independence is dropped. Under this QALY model, estimation of a risk parameter for one health state in combination with a riskless health value elicitation in relation to any other health state, determine the curvature of the utility function. The exponentiated linear QALY model (or expo-linear QALY model), is the only QALY model that is known to violate utility independence, but is tractable for decision analysis. Keeney and Raiffa (1993, p. 259, Eq. (3.69)) first put forth this model for use in cases when utility independence is violated, but until now it has not received an axiomatic treatment.

Section snippets

A comparison of approaches for minimizing the role of risky choices in QALY evaluations

QALYs are the most important outcome measure in medical decision making. Therefore, the study of how best to represent and elicit preferences using QALY models deserves attention. Maas and Wakker (1994) explored ways to minimize the role of risky choice in the axiomatization and elicitation of QALYs by introducing riskless value conditions. A reduction in the role of risky choice is desirable for several reasons. Risky choices are often unreliable and subject to bias (Johnson & Schkade, 1989).

Structural assumptions

Let T=[0,M] be a real interval representing possible survival durations. At times, we will need to refer to the strictly positive survival duration, T−{0}. For convenience, let T+=T−{0}. Let H be a nonempty set of health states. Let H×T denote the Cartesian product set. We denote ordered pairs in H×T by juxtaposed symbols, e.g., ax∈H×T. Let be a binary preference relation on H×T, and let ≻ and ∼ be the asymmetric and symmetric parts of . A health state a is worse-than-death if axay for

Constant proportional time tradeoff and decision under risk

In this section, we extend our results to situations involving decisions under risk. We begin by assuming binary rank-dependent utility theory. This theory constitutes the framework of assumptions regarding preference under risk within which extensions of the preceding theorems will be developed. Next we postulate a condition that is self-evident in the domain of health (the zero condition). Under the aforementioned assumptions, we show that simple preference conditions concerning risk posture

Conclusions

Constant proportional time trade-off together with mild conditions implies an additive riskless value function and places powerful constraints on the functional form utility when well-known risk posture conditions hold. In this paper, we have outlined how CP-TTO in combination with risk posture conditions leads to several different QALY representations.

By invoking CP-TTO in the context of risk posture conditions, the role of risky choice in QALY elicitation is reduced to risk parameter

Acknowledgements

We thank two anonymous reviewers. Their comments substantially improved the quality of this paper. This work was supported by grants from the National Institutes of Health, National Center for Medical Rehabilitation Research (NIH-NCMRR: K01HD01221), and the National Institute for Disability and Rehabilitation Research (NIDRR: H133A98023). The usual disclaimer applies.

References (29)

  • U. Ebert

    Measurement of inequalityAn attempt at unification and generalization

    Social Choice and Welfare

    (1988)
  • J.-C. Falmagne

    Random conjoint measurement and loudness summation

    Psychological Review

    (1976)
  • Hershey et al.

    Probability versus certainty equivalence methods in utility assessment: Are they equivalent?

    Management Science

    (1985)
  • E. Johnson et al.

    Bias in utility assessmentFurther evidence and explanation

    Management Science

    (1989)
  • Cited by (15)

    • Estimating a WTP-based value of a QALY: The 'chained' approach

      2013, Social Science and Medicine
      Citation Excerpt :

      For example, it may well be the case that the true model is not linear in duration and that doubling the duration of a health state does not double the perceived loss of health. Thus, our results may – at least in part- indicate that the basic linear QALY model does not adequately reflect respondents' underlying preference structures (see Abellan-Perpinan, Pinto-Prades, Mendez-Martinez, & Badia-Llach, 2006; Doctor & Miyamoto, 2003; Kvamme, Gyrd-Hansen, Abel Olsen, & Sonbo Kristiansen, 2010 for discussion of the use of non-linear QALY models). Although not discussed in detail above, there is another finding of the research that may raise some questions about the methodology underlying the chained approach.

    • Axioms for health care resource allocation

      2005, Journal of Health Economics
    • Organism-level models: When mechanisms and statistics fail us

      2014, Journal of Physics: Conference Series
    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text