Elsevier

Consciousness and Cognition

Volume 20, Issue 4, December 2011, Pages 1697-1704
Consciousness and Cognition

What are self-generated actions?

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2011.09.006Get rights and content

Abstract

The concept of self-generated action is controversial, despite extensive study of its neural basis. Why is this concept so troublesome? We analyse the concept of self-generated action as employed by Passingham et al., 2010a, Passingham et al., 2010b. There are two definitions of self-generated action; as operant action and as underdetermined action. The latter draws on subjective experience. Experiments on action awareness suggest that experience may not be a good guide for defining self-generated action. Nevertheless, we agree with Passingham and colleagues that self-generated actions exist distinct from operant actions. But defining ‘self-generated’ by the degree of involvement of an endogenous process risks regress. We sketch an alternative account of self-generated action that tries to avoid these problems to make self-generated actions accessible to experimental science.

Highlights

► The concept of self-generated action is controversial. ► Self-generated action as underdetermined action relies on the experience of an agentic self. ► Studies have shown that this experience of agent causation may be illusionary. ► We suggest an alternative view based on integration of multiple information sources. ► This opens self-generated actions to scientific study and removes dualistic flavour.

Introduction

The scientific study of self-generated action, and its relation to volition and conscious experience, has long been controversial. For example, Libet’s finding that the onset of the readiness-potential precedes reports of conscious intention (Libet, Gleason, Wright, & Pearl, 1983) continues to provoke discussions about ‘conscious free will’. While the neural basis of self-generated actions has been studied extensively (Eccles, 1982, Fleming et al., 2009, Okano and Tanji, 1987, Romo and Schultz, 1987, Shima et al., 1991, Thaler et al., 1995), the concept of self-generated action remains difficult. Why is this concept of self-generated action so troublesome?

In a recent exchange between Passingham et al., 2010a, Passingham et al., 2010b and Nachev and Husain (2010), the difficulties with the concept of self-generated actions have become apparent. This exchange exemplifies differences in opinion in the field of study of self-generated actions. As such it is informative about why it is that the study of self-generated action has been plagued by controversies and debate.

In this article, we first review the debate between Passingham et al., 2010a, Passingham et al., 2010b and Nachev and Husain (2010). Then, we take a closer look at the literature on self-generated actions that Passingham et al., 2010a, Passingham et al., 2010b refer to for support. There are two definitions of self-generated action: self-generated actions can be defined either as operant actions, or as underdetermined action. We accept the first definition as a scientifically viable conception of self-generated action. By contrast, we argue that the definition of self-generated action as underdetermined actions draws from subjective experience, in particular regarding the (often implicit) idea of the involvement of a self in self-generated action. We review literature on action awareness to show that subjective experience is not a good guide for defining self-generated action. Then, we assess whether brain anatomy can provide arguments for relating the self to self-generated action. After exploring the concept of ‘endogenous process’ (Passingham, Bengtsson, & Lau, 2010b) in relation to self-generated action as underdetermined action, we sketch a novel definition of self-generated action as complex integration. This approach suggests new directions for the future study of self-generated action.

In the article that sparked off the controversy, Passingham, Bengtsson, and Lau, review and endorse the claim that the medial frontal cortex in general, and the supplementary motor cortex in particular, are crucially involved in self-generated action (2010a). Actions are self-generated, according to the authors, if these actions are not uniquely specified by external cues (Passingham et al., 2010b, Passingham et al., 2010a). Passingham et al. (2010a) discuss and dismiss challenges to their view, for example that differences in neural activity for self-generated compared to externally triggered action may be explained solely by differential demands on working memory, increased conflict processing, and increased task-complexity (p. 17). The authors speculate that internal as opposed to external cues could give rise to self-generated action. Internal cues could are, for example, one’s own preceding actions (e.g., Halsband and Passingham, 1982, Passingham, 1987), elapsed time (e.g., Mita, Mushiake, Shima, Matsuzaka, & Tanji, 2009), or (changing) behavioural goals (e.g., Kennerley, Dahmubed, Lara, & Wallis, 2009).

Then, Passingham and colleagues expand their claim: They propose that the medial frontal cortex underlies self-reflection, episodic memory, and self-referential thoughts during ‘mind-wandering’. More generally, they propose that information related to the self is processed on the medial frontal surface of the brain. By contrast, information about the external environment is processed on the lateral surface of the brain. This proposal is consistent with what is currently known about the anatomical connections of the medial and lateral surfaces of the brain (Passingham et al., 2010a, p. 19).

Nachev and Husain question the possibility of investigating self-generated action scientifically on purely conceptual grounds: “… the contrast between internally- and externally-guided actions is empirically intractable.” (Nachev & Husain, 2010). According to Nachev and Husain, internal cues are by definition hidden from any experimenter’s view (p. 192). The invisibility of cues, however, does not rule out their existence or importance for behaviour. The effects of external cues on action can be investigated using conventional experimental methods. However, because these methods cannot or are not used to investigate the effects internal cues on action, there are a myriad of possibly relevant internal cues and we cannot determine what they are. Therefore, comparison between self-generated and externally triggered action cannot yield scientifically meaningful data (Nachev & Husain, 2010).

Passingham and colleagues (2010b) reply to this criticism is twofold. First, they state that the number and nature of cues, internal and external, can be controlled for by carefully balancing task features such as complexity and level of conflict, between self-generated and externally-triggered action. Second, they state that the distinction between externally-trigged and self-generated action is a matter of degree, rather than a sharp divide: “… it would be fallacious to claim that there are no external components in self-generated actions and no internal components in externally generated actions.” (Passingham et al., 2010b). Rather: “It is the difference between two conditions [i.e. self-generated and externally-trigged] that can be said to reflect a difference in the degree of involvement of an endogenous processes.” (Passingham et al., 2010b, p. 194).

Passingham’s et al. answer (2010b) may not fully address Nachev and Husain’s criticism. For example, if removing external cues were, by itself, to increase task complexity, then one could not modulate the self-generatedness of an action while at the same time equating for complexity. In this article, instead of taking sides in this debate, we take a closer look at the literature of self-generated action that Passingham et al., 2010a, Passingham et al., 2010b refer to for support. In particular, we focus on how it is that self-generated actions are defined and operationalised in these studies.

Section snippets

The self in self-generated actions

Passingham et al. (2010a) define self-generated action as operant action (2010a, p. 16). They further clarify that the self-generatedness of an action is determined by the absence of specification by external cues. But this clarification implies something which goes beyond the original definition of self-generated actions as operant actions. Crucially, we suggest that studies on self-generated actions do not form one homogenous body of evidence, but can be divided into two distinct types based

Self-generated actions as complex integration

Self-generated action as underdetermined action is problematic, in particular the putative link between a self and self-generated action. Nevertheless, we acknowledge the sense that there are actions that are neither externally-trigged nor operant. We propose an alternative interpretation of the continuum between externally-triggered and self-generated action to introduce a novel definition of self-generated action which, we hope, is scientifically viable: Self-generated actions are the motor

Concluding remarks

We agree with Passingham et al. (2010a) that actions are self-generated by degree. Since continua do not naturally produce category boundaries, classifying any single action as either self-generated or externally triggered may be difficult. Furthermore, we agree that the concept of self-generated action serves an important function. But there are two distinct concepts of self-generated action in the literature: self-generated action as operant action and as underdetermined action.

Acknowledgments

F.S. was funded by a UCL Graduate School Research Scholarship. PH was supported by a Leverhulme Trust Major Research Fellowship. We would like to thank Elisa Filevich, Guido Orgs, and Cressida Gaukroger for helpful discussion. Finally, we are indebted to our three anonymous reviewers for very thoughtful comments and helpful criticism.

References (53)

  • K. Linser et al.

    Unconscious modulation of the conscious experience of voluntary control

    Cognition

    (2007)
  • J.W. Moore et al.

    Modulating the sense of agency with external cues

    Consciousness and Cognition

    (2009)
  • P. Nachev et al.

    Action and the fallacy of the “internal”: Comment on Passingham et al.

    Trends in Cognitive Sciences

    (2010)
  • S.S. Obhi et al.

    On the signals underlying conscious awareness of action

    Cognition

    (2009)
  • M.P.A. Page

    What can’t functional neuroimaging tell the cognitive psychologist?

    Cortex

    (2006)
  • R.E. Passingham et al.

    Medial frontal cortex: From self-generated action to reflection on one’s own performance

    Trends in Cognitive Sciences

    (2010)
  • R.E. Passingham et al.

    Is it fallacious to talk of self-generated action?: Response to Nachev and Husain

    Trends in Cognitive Sciences

    (2010)
  • M. Synofzik et al.

    Me or not me – An optimal integration of agency cues?

    Consciousness and Cognition

    (2009)
  • D.M. Wegner

    The mind’s best trick: How we experience conscious will

    Trends in Cognitive Sciences

    (2003)
  • M.L. Anderson

    Evolution of cognitive function via redeployment of brain areas

    The Neuroscientist

    (2007)
  • W.P. Banks et al.

    We infer rather than perceive the moment we decided to act

    Psychological Science

    (2009)
  • S.L. Bengtsson et al.

    Motivation to do well enhances responses to errors and self-monitoring

    Cerebral Cortex

    (2009)
  • J.E. Bogen et al.

    Wernicke’s region – Where is it?

    Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences

    (1976)
  • M. Brass et al.

    To do or not to do: The neural signature of self-control

    Journal of Neuroscience

    (2007)
  • B. Brembs

    Towards a scientific concept of free will as a biological trait: Spontaneous actions and decision-making in invertebrates

    Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences

    (2010)
  • A.D. Craig

    How do you feel? Interoception: The sense of the physiological condition of the body

    Nature Reviews Neuroscience

    (2002)
  • Cited by (42)

    • Given the option, people avoid incongruent responses in a dual-tasking situation

      2022, Acta Psychologica
      Citation Excerpt :

      The research purposes of the use of free choice tasks included viewing them as approximations of voluntary, self-generated action (e.g., Brass & Haggard, 2008; Herwig, Prinz, & Waszak, 2007; Herwig & Waszak, 2012), a usage closer to the one found in the present work. They have also been called (Frith, 2013) or empirically compared to (Naefgen & Janczyk, 2018) random generation tasks and have been said to be tasks that are either underdetermined or determined by uncontrolled internal cues (Schüür & Haggard, 2011). Our goal here was not to induce conflict (like the response-response conflict Berlyne postulated) but to give participants a chance to avoid conflict.

    • Freely chosen and instructed actions are terminated by different neural mechanisms revealed by kinematics-informed EEG

      2019, NeuroImage
      Citation Excerpt :

      In these comparisons, volition has been associated with brain structures, especially in the medial prefrontal cortex, that exhibit elevated activity when an action is self-selected relative to when that action is instructed (Krieghoff et al., 2011; Brass et al., 2013; Zapparoli et al., 2017). However, these findings have been controversial and the topic of an extensive debate due to the difficulty in specifying and interpreting how actions were “self-selected” in these experiments and the numerous confounding differences (Lau et al., 2004; Botvinick et al., 2004; Nachev et al., 2005; Nachev and Husain, 2010; Passingham et al., 2010; Schüür and Haggard, 2011; Bode et al., 2013; Brass et al., 2013). An example of such a confounding difference is the sensory and perceptual demand to identify a stimulus-defined instruction that has no equivalent for freely selected actions.

    • Subliminal modulation of voluntary action experience: A neuropsychological investigation

      2017, Cortex
      Citation Excerpt :

      We suggest that one key input to the experience of agency is a readout of an internal volitional signal that precedes endogenous actions. This internal signal, however, could be influenced by externally-triggered signals from the outside environment (affordances): volition is not independent of the current environment and response space (Schüür & Haggard, 2011). In the case of healthy participants and the unaffected hand of TP, this external signal is integrated into the internal volitional signal to facilitate action preparation.

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text