The neural, evolutionary, developmental, and bodily basis of metaphor

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2005.11.001Get rights and content

Abstract

We propose that there are four fundamental kinds of metaphor that are uniquely mapped onto specific brain “networks” and present preliterate (i.e., evolutionary, including before the appearance of written language in the historical record), prelinguistic (i.e., developmental, before the appearance of speech in human development), and extralinguistic (i.e., neuropsychological, cognitive) evidence supportive of this view. We contend that these basic metaphors are largely nonconceptual and entail (a) perceptual–perceptual, (b) cross-modal, (c) movement–movement, and (d) perceptual-affective mappings that, at least, in the initial stages of processing may operate largely outside of conscious awareness. In opposition to our basic metaphor theory (BmT), the standard theory (SmT) maintains that metaphor is a conceptual mapping from some base domain to some target domain and/or represents class-inclusion (categorical) assertions. The SmT captures aspects of secondary or conceptual metaphoric relations but not primary or basic metaphoric relations in our view. We believe our theory (BmT) explains more about how people actually recognize or create metaphoric associations across disparate domains of experience partly because they are “pre-wired” to make these links.

Introduction

We propose that there are four fundamental kinds of metaphor that are uniquely mapped onto specific brain “networks” and present preliterate (i.e., evolutionary, including before the appearance of written language in the historical record), prelinguistic (i.e., developmental, before the appearance of speech in human development), and extralinguistic (i.e., neuropsychological, cognitive) evidence supportive of this view. We contend that these basic metaphors are largely nonconceptual and entail (a) perceptual–perceptual, (b) cross-modal (synesthetic), (c) movement–movement, and (d) perceptual-affective mappings that, at least, in the initial stages of processing may operate outside of conscious awareness. That is, they are informationally encapsulated (Fodor, 1983), “pre-wired” (Marcus, 2004), and probably universal across human populations (Brown (1991), Brown (1999), Brown (2000)). In opposition to our basic metaphor theory (BmT), the standard theory (SmT) maintains that metaphor is a conceptual mapping from some base domain to some target domain (e.g., Gentner, Holyoak & Kokinov, 2001; Lakoff & Johnson, 1980) and/or represents class-inclusion (categorical) assertions (e.g., Glucksberg, 2003).

For instance, Gentner and colleagues (Gentner et al., 2001; Gentner & Markman, 1997) argue that similarity, including metaphoric similarity as well as analogy, involves a process of “structure alignment”—a one-to-one correspondence between mapped elements and “systematicity”—a matching of connected systems of relations. Metaphors, however, map both systems of relations (e.g., atomic structure is like a solar system) and attributes of objects (e.g., “His hand was like a vise”) depending on the type of the metaphor. This differentiation of similarity, however, conflates analogy with metaphor and BmT theory suggests that metaphor is a separate species, at least for the metaphorical relations subsumed by it. On the other hand, Glucksberg and colleagues (Glucksberg, 2003; Glucksberg & Keysar, 1993) contend that metaphors are more properly thought of as “implicit class-inclusion relations.” For instance, the metaphorical statement, “Cigarettes are time bombs,” is a class-inclusion assertion in which the terms, “cigarettes” and “time bombs” are absorbed under the superordinate category, “time bombs.” Nevertheless, what is left out of both of these accounts is how people actually go about selecting which relations, which attributes or which terms to attend to in the first place.

While Glucksberg and colleagues maintain that metaphoric statements are apprehended as ordinary language—“quickly and automatically”—it would appear that metaphor comprehension probably occurs in conscious awareness because it involves, among other things, ongoing decisions about how to respond to mutually constituted social interactions (e.g., Speaker A: “Cigarettes are time bombs.” Speaker B: “Yes, I stopped smoking several years ago”); although the authors do not confront this thorny aspect of metaphoric language—that it often serves some conscious social purpose. Indeed, Gentner and colleagues indicate that analogy and metaphor involve more abstract conceptual relations and presumably entail some conscious mechanisms.

People make analogical and metaphoric inferences based on higher-order connecting relations (p. 239).

Similar accounts are found elsewhere in the literature and are widespread, i.e., metaphor involves the mapping of conceptual domains at high levels of abstraction and entails some conscious mechanisms (e.g., Fauconnier & Turner (1998), Fauconnier & Turner (2002); Lakoff & Johnson, 1980). Lakoff (1993), however, suggests that conceptual metaphor is largely unconscious and automatic like ordinary language and this largely unconscious substrate of our conceptual system “contains thousands of conventional metaphorical mappings” (p. 245). We criticize this view below under “Alternative Theories of Early Metaphor.” In any event, the nonconscious mechanisms operating outside awareness are notoriously difficult to pin down (Allen & Reber, 1998).

To be sure, consciousness deals with situations that require novel and nonstereotypical responses. Nonconscious mechanisms, however, function to deal with stereotypical forms of behavior conditioned by evolution for immediate and efficient use (Koch, 2004; Searle, 2005). We propose that the kinds of basic metaphoric relations in BmT are largely nonconscious and automatic: Notwithstanding individual differences, we might easily perceive a plate of spaghetti as a collection of worms or a stop sign as a popsicle (perceptual–perceptual metaphors), a spinning top as a ballerina (movement–movement metaphor), a front of a car as smiling (perceptual-affective metaphor) or music as sad (cross-modal metaphor; see Seitz (2001a), Seitz (2005)). That is, they involve extensive automaticity including implicit perception, memory, and thought; they are fast and independent (Marcus, 2004); they are engaged by specific environmental stimuli; and they are largely innate (Kihlstrom (1987), Kihlstrom (2002); see below). Cytowic (2002a), Cytowic (2002b) makes a related case for synesthesia arguing that that it is automatic, involuntary, and inborn.

SmT thus captures aspects of secondary or conceptual metaphoric relations but not primary or basic metaphoric relations in our view. We think our theory BmT explains more about how people actually create or recognize metaphoric associations across disparate domains of experience partly because they are “pre-wired” to make these links. That is, we propose that humans have specialized neural subsystems for metaphoric understanding and production that are fine-tuned by experience and continuously modulated by underlying genetic mechanisms (Marcus, 2004).

The fundamental ability to link disparate sensory, perceptual, enactive, and affective domains can be described as an inter-, poly-, or multisensory ability or supra-, trans-, hetero- or multimodular capacity (Calvert, 2001, Seitz, 1997). That is, these basic metaphoric relations (BmT) rely on central sensory, perceptual, and affective mechanisms that relate percepts and affects across dissimilar psychological domains based on relations within and between brain areas or “networks” (see below). For instance, biological constraints in the maturation of the intersensory areas in the mid- and frontal areas of the brain underlie synesthetic metaphor or the ability to link disparate sensory modalities (Marks, 1996; Marks & Bornstein, 1987; Marks, Hammeal, & Bornstein, 1987; Ramachandran & Hubbard (2001a), Ramachandran & Hubbard (2001b)).

Similarly, we have shown that the ability to link the physical and psychological domains (“psychological–physical metaphor;” Cicone, Gardner, & Winner, 1981) is based on the earlier ability to attribute affective properties to inanimate objects or what we have called “physiognomic metaphor” (Seitz, 1998b; Seitz & Beilin, 1987). For instance, whereas synesthetic metaphor is largely biological constrained, appears to derive from an inborn sense of similarity or comparison, and relies less on learning and development—that is to say, is largely intuitive (see below)—psychological–physical metaphor violates category boundaries based on learned conceptual relations (whether from informal experience or formal learning) and the probable rejection (whether conscious or not) of cultural and linguistic conventions. This is, at least, true of novel metaphors if not conventional ones (Gentner et al., 2001) as Quinn (1991) has argued: Metaphors are typically chosen by speakers because they are already part of existing cultural understandings.

Nevertheless, the ability to relate the perceptual and affective domains originates in the biological capacity to impute affective properties to inanimate and animate objects (Seitz & Beilin, 1987). Autistic children who lack this capacity are unable to attribute affective properties to social or nonsocial objects or use or apprehend metaphoric language (Baron-Cohen, Leslie, & Frith, 1985; Leslie & Frith, 1988; Seitz, 1996)—notwithstanding Kanner's (1946) earlier but incorrect use of the term “metaphoric language” in autistic children (see Seitz, 1996)—as are brain damaged adults with alexithymia (Brothers, 1989) and adults with forms of prosopagnosia in which there is damage to anterior regions of area V4 in the inferior temporal lobe that underlie both affective recognition and expression in the face (Zeki, 1999).

Section snippets

The role of intuition in the basic and standard theory

BmT posits that these four fundamental metaphors (i.e., perceptual–perceptual, cross-modal, movement–movement, and perceptual-affective relations) operate outside of awareness and manifest extensive automaticity in the initial stages of processing (Kihlstrom, 2002). That is, they are engaged by specific environmental stimuli (e.g., shape, size, texture, pitch, rhythm, rate, intensity, and spatial location) and the stimulus may not be consciously registered in its initial encounter. For

Perceptual metaphor

It has been amply documented that, early on, very young children (i.e., the beginning of the third year of life) are able to exploit the perceptual features of shape, color, texture, and size in making metaphorical associations in renaming single objects or pictures (e.g., Seitz (1997), Seitz (1998a), Seitz (1998b); Winner, McCarthy, & Gardner, 1980; Winner, McCarthy, Kleinman, & Gardner, 1979). For instance, a preschool child may refer to a plate of spaghetti as a “bunch of worms” or a

Perceptual and synesthetic metaphor

Merlin Donald (1991) has suggested that in the evolution of primates, metaphoric or “integrative” thought originated in early primate “episodic culture” associated with the initial appearance of perceptual metaphor including cross-modal associations. For what reason would these abilities have evolved in early primates? Early primate cognition would have necessitated the ability to engage in complex event discrimination (“episodic cognition”) and to react to complex patterns of stimuli based on

Comparative evidence

Comparative studies across species indicate that the core abilities underlying metaphor—such as the ability to form mental representations of perceived objects (i.e., to categorize and form concepts of objects), integrate sensory and affective experiences of those objects (i.e., cross-modal transfer), and form relational concepts—may be shared with other birds and mammals (Hauser, 2000; Pepperberg, 1999; Tomasello & Call, 1997). For instance, in all investigated primate species there is

Motor and nonmotor areas of the brain overlap

The evidence for the bodily or “embodied” basis of early metaphor (BmT) is fourfold. In the first instance, many of the so-called motor structures in the brain (e.g., cerebellum, basal ganglia, and supplementary motor, premotor and motor cortices) play a significant role in cognition (Seitz, 2000a). For example, the acquisition in children of two-word utterances during the second half of the second year of life is revealing. Roger Brown (1973) has documented that eleven types of sensorimotor

Historical background

Initial observations of the brain basis of basic metaphoric abilities (BmT) indicated that intersensory correlations as well as physiognomic experiences derived from a primitive, amodal core in which perceptual, affective, and motoric aspects of experience were undifferentiated in early development (Werner (1948), Werner (1955), Werner (1978); Werner & Kaplan, 1963/1984). Werner termed these synesthetic associations “comparison metaphors.” More recent studies have shown that these synesthetic

“Primary” metaphor

The foregoing description of four species of early metaphor and their emergence early in development is by no means the only perspective on early metaphor. For instance, Lakoff and Johnson (1999) allege that there are several hundred, universal metaphors that are acquired early in development. For example, “IMPORTANT IS BIG” “DIFFICULTIES ARE BURDENS,” and “LINEAR SCALES ARE PATHS.” These universal, conceptual, and linguistic metaphors (“primary” metaphor, Lakoff & Johnson, 1999) are acquired

Conclusions

We believe that our BmT explains more about how people actually recognize or create basic or primary metaphoric associations across disparate domains of experience than does that SmT partly because humans are “pre-wired” to make these linkages. These basic metaphoric equivalences include perceptual–perceptual, movement–movement, cross-modal (synesthetic), and perceptual-affective relations that we demonstrated are uniquely mapped onto brain “networks.” We presented three major strands of

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank Professor Harry Beilin of The Graduate Center/City University of New York (CUNY), Professor John Kennedy of the University of Toronto, Professor Elkhonon Goldberg of NYU School of Medicine, and several anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments and suggestions on earlier drafts of this manuscript.

References (137)

  • J.F. Kihlstrom

    The unconscious

  • A.N. Meltzoff et al.

    Imitation, memory, and the representation of persons

    Infant Behavior and Development: An International and Multidisciplinary Journal

    (2002)
  • G. Rizzolatti et al.

    Language within our grasp

    Trends in Neurosciences

    (1998)
  • C. Allen et al.

    Species of mind: The philosophy and biology of cognitive ethology

    (1997)
  • R. Allen et al.

    Unconscious intelligence

  • E. Anati

    World rock art: The primordial language

    (1994)
  • S.E. Asch

    On the use of metaphor in the description of persons

  • S.E. Asch et al.

    The development of double-function terms in children

  • M.D. Bownds

    The biology of mind: Origins and structures of mind, brain, and consciousness

    (1999)
  • L. Brothers

    A biological perspective on empathy

    American Journal of Psychiatry

    (1989)
  • D.E. Brown

    Human universals

    (1991)
  • D.E. Brown

    Human universals

  • D.E. Brown

    Human universals and their implications

  • R. Brown

    A first language: The early stages

    (1973)
  • R.W. Brown

    Is a boulder sweet or sour?

    Contemporary Psychology

    (1958)
  • G.A. Calvert

    Crossmodal processing in the human brain: Insights from functional neuroimaging studies

    Cerebral Cortex

    (2001)
  • M. Cicone et al.

    Understanding the psychology in psychological metaphors

    Journal of Child Language

    (1981)
  • M. Corballis

    The gestural origins of language

    American Scientist

    (1999)
  • M. Corballis

    From hand to mouth: The origins of language

    (2002)
  • R.E. Cytowic

    The man who tasted shapes

    (1993)
  • R.E. Cytowic

    Synesthesia: Phenomenology and neuropsychology

    Psyche

    (1995)
  • R.E. Cytowic

    Touching tastes, seeing smells—and shaking up brain science

    Cerebrum

    (2002)
  • R.E. Cytowic

    Synesthesia: A union of the senses

    (2002)
  • A.R. Damasio et al.

    Cortical systems for retrieval of concrete knowledge: The convergence zone framework

  • C.H. Dent

    The developmental importance of motion information in perceiving and describing metaphoric similarity

    Child Development

    (1984)
  • S. Dey

    Synaesthesia and synaesthetic metaphors

    Psyche

    (1996)
  • O. Devinsky et al.

    Norman Geschwind: Selected papers on language, epilepsy, and behavior

    (1997)
  • M. Donald

    Origins of the modern mind: Three stages in the evolution of culture and cognition

    (1991)
  • G. Fauconnier et al.

    Principles of conceptual integration

  • G. Fauconnier et al.

    The way we think: Conceptual blending and the mind's hidden complexities

    (2002)
  • J.A. Fodor

    The modularity of mind

    (1983)
  • J.M. Fuster

    Cortex and mind: Unifying cognition

    (2003)
  • H. Gardner

    Metaphors and modalities: How children project polar adjectives onto diverse domains

    Child Development

    (1974)
  • H. Gardner

    Developmental psychology: An introduction

    (1982)
  • D. Gentner et al.

    Structure mapping in analogy and similarity

    American Psychologist

    (1997)
  • N. Geschwind

    The development of the brain and the evolution of language

  • S. Glucksberg et al.

    How metaphors work

  • E.H. Gombrich

    Meditations on a hobby horse and other essays on the theory of art

    (1963)
  • N. Goodman

    Languages of art: An approach to a theory of symbols

    (1976)
  • Cited by (31)

    • Are we all born synaesthetic? Examining the neonatal synaesthesia hypothesis

      2013, Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews
      Citation Excerpt :

      Notice here that in this piece we have focused on early development of sensory matching, but obviously the developmental trend continues and later involves acquisition of metaphor in pre-schoolers (see Gardner, 1974; Wagner et al., 1981). However, this is a topic for another day (see also Seitz, 2005). Here we have also not shown why this account could explain the importance of crossmodal changes (vs. static display) in the acquisition and sensitivity to crossmodal correspondences, as has been documented more recently (Jeschonek et al., 2012; Walker et al., 2010), or the crossmodal transfer between touch and vision for shapes, or pathological failures in multisensory integration and crossmodal correspondences that are supposed to exist in autistic children and adults (see David et al., 2011, for a recent review) – or the crossmodal correspondences that are known to exist in animals (e.g., Ettlinger, 1961; Premack and Premack, 2003; Spence and Deroy, 2012a; see also Schiller, 1935, for an intriguing early study conducted with fish; note that yet almost no one extrapolates from such results to the conclusion that the animals concerned must therefore be synaesthetic (see Callaway, 2011, for a solitary exception).

    • " Symbol formation and the embodied self: A microgenetic case-study examination of the transition to symbolic communication in scribbling activities from 14 to 31 months of age"

      2011, New Ideas in Psychology
      Citation Excerpt :

      This emerging closure partaking of “physiognomic,”15 affective-connotative qualities may potentially be communicated as an animated event/form (see expressive/physiognomic perception, Arnheim, 1974). Hence, a primary potentiality for the “metaphorization” of space—an analogical/metaphoric attribution of physiognomic qualities in “configural forms”—arises which, at least in this stage of processing, may operate largely outside awareness (see primary visual metaphors in Seitz, 2005). Example: Yiannis (1 year, 8 months, 21 days), three days before Yiannis showed his first differentiation16 between MINE and YOURS.17

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text