Skip to main content
Log in

On serendipity in science: discovery at the intersection of chance and wisdom

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

‘Serendipity’ is a category used to describe discoveries in science that occur at the intersection of chance and wisdom. In this paper, I argue for understanding serendipity in science as an emergent property of scientific discovery, describing an oblique relationship between the outcome of a discovery process and the intentions that drove it forward. The recognition of serendipity is correlated with an acknowledgment of the limits of expectations about potential sources of knowledge. I provide an analysis of serendipity in science as a defense of this definition and its implications, drawing from theoretical and empirical research on experiences of serendipity as they occur in science and elsewhere. I focus on three interrelated features of serendipity in science. First, there are variations of serendipity. The process of serendipitous discovery can be complex. Second, a valuable outcome must be obtained before reflection upon the significance of the unexpected observation or event in respect to that outcome can take place. Therefore, serendipity is retrospectively categorized. Third, the primacy of epistemic expectations is elucidated. Finally, I place this analysis within discussions in philosophy of science regarding the impact of interpersonal competition upon the number and significance of scientific discoveries. Thus, the analysis of serendipity offered in this paper contributes to discussions about the social-epistemological aspects of scientific discovery and has normative implications for the structure of epistemically effective scientific communities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Walpole refers in this passage to the Princes of Serendip, characters in a fairy tale who inspired him to label this phenomenon ‘serendipity’ because of how they make valuable use of accidental observations.

  2. Of course, in philosophical discussion about the logic or rationality of scientific discovery, there is a deep and complicated debate concerning abduction (see work by Peirce, Paavola, Hanson, Hintikka, for example). How well abduction works as a description of the reasoning involved in some cases of serendipity (see the following paragraphs) is a topic I pursue elsewhere, and is outside of the scope of this paper.

  3. This is also frequently called synchronicity in the serendipity literature, following Jung: “simultaneous occurrence of two meaningfully but not causally connected events” (as quoted in Liestman 1992, p. 527). Liestman’s (1992) use of synchronicity as one category of serendipity in library research is picked up by several others, from fields such as computer–human interaction (Kefalidou and Sharples 2016), education (Nutefall and Ryder 2010) and information studies (Foster and Ellis 2014). Synchronicity is also appealed to by organizational and management theorists (see Cunha 2005 for further references). However, I follow Lawley and Tompkins (2008), who draw a distinction between synchronicity and serendipity, because the former is recognized immediately whereas the latter is not (see Sect. 2).

  4. There are many chance aspects of even this observation, including the perfect temperature fluctuations in London at the right time, an open door to a stairwell, and Fleming’s vacation (Diggins 1999, p. 87). Chance marked the path to penicillin’s mass-production as well—to name one instance, lab assistant Mary Hunt was at the local market when she picked up a moldy cantaloupe, which led to the discovery of a better medium for penicillin’s production, despite the hundreds of samples sent from afar to the lab for just that purpose. The insightful assistant in this case was, however, rewarded with a nickname—‘Moldy Mary’—rather than a Nobel Prize.

  5. A possible exception is Kohn’s (1989) book, Fortune and Failure: Missed Opportunities and Chance Discoveries in Science. However, as with the example given by Barber and Fox, the ‘forgotten’ discoveries in this book are only seen as such in light of the discoveries that were (later) actually made.

  6. Given the quotation from Nickles above, one might extend this retrospectivity to many discovery processes, but since it would not extend to all processes categorized as discovery processes (since some are indeed intentional, for example, and therefore prospective), ‘serendipity’ remains a particular classification within that broader category (ie: a kind of discovery process that is recognized retrospectively).

  7. Of course, in some cases this timeline is collapsed, such as when the value of the discovery is clear at the time of observation. One example might be when a collector of fine garden gnomes happens by chance to visit a friend whose neighbor is holding a garage sale and selling a gnome whose value the collector is able to identify immediately. But more often, including in the examples Walpole himself gives and (I would argue) almost always in the case of scientific discovery, multiple steps are required to reveal the true value of the unexpected finding. And still, the gnome collector could not have known her visit to the friend would be serendipitous beforehand (or it wouldn’t have been, by definition).

  8. Cunha (2005) and Lawley and Tompkins (2008) developed the first process models through an analysis of case studies and the literature. The later articles cited here refer to studies that confirmed and refined that model via empirical research (i.e.: interviews).

  9. See Anjum and Mumford (2017) for an example of an account of emergent properties as those properties that do not belong to the parts but rather arise from an interaction between parts as novel properties of the whole.

  10. Nassim Taleb provides a similar approach to what he calls Black Swans—catastrophic events that came by surprise (2007). Taleb highlights the fact that although in retrospect we are often able to explain how Black Swan events occurred, cognitive biases prevent us from predicting their occurrence beforehand. However, even if we were perfectly aware of our cognitive biases, Black Swans would still occur.

  11. Most notably, Fleming himself, who humbly declared during his Nobel Prize Award speech that, “My only merit is that I did not neglect the observation and that I pursued the subject as a bacteriologist” (Fleming 1945).

  12. I am far from alone in pointing out, for instance, that others had made similar observations but had lacked the timeliness and social connections that Fleming had. A fairly well-known example is the French graduate student Ernest Duchesne, whose dissertation reporting on the therapeutic effects of another Penicillium mold was submitted in 1897. Duchesne’s work remained unknown and he died a few years later, however, and so his preliminary efforts were not taken up to be part of the discovery process that ultimately led to penicillin (see Copeland 2015, pp. 63ff for this and other examples).

  13. Aspects of these first two questions are often discussed under the problem of the division of cognitive labour (see Kitcher 1990; Weisburg and Muldoon 2009, for examples).

  14. I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for drawing my attention to the relevance of this discussion.

  15. As Strevens (2017) points out, not only data is of value when it comes to sharing scientific knowledge. In keeping with the variations of serendipity I have described above, all sorts of information might have unexpected value, enabling a discovery by making it timely or by creating a social connection between scientists that leads to the exchange of further information, for example.

  16. A further factor in the discussion over Franklin’s contribution to this discovery concerns whether Watson and Crick illegitimately gained access to Franklin’s data. Michelle Gibbons offers insight into the relevance of that discussion for determining Franklin’s role and offers a complementary approach to the discovery in her article, “Reassessing Discovery” (Gibbons 2012).

  17. One can assume there will always be unexpected observations or events, so long as scientists fall short of omniscience.

  18. Howard Gest points to a similar factor in his recounting of serendipity in the isolation of the vitamin C molecule—the fact that one group of scientists had a much faster and less costly test available to them allowed for their belated, yet successful involvement in that discovery process (Gest 1997, p. 23).

References

  • Andriani, P. (2017). Exaptation, serendipity and aging. Mechanisms of Ageing and Development, 163(April), 30–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anjum, R. L., & Mumford, S. (2017). Emergence and demergence. In M. Paulini, P. Orilia, & F. Orilia (Eds.), Philosophical and scientific perspectives on downward causation (pp. 92–109). New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. H. (2003). Chase, chance, and creativity: The lucky art of novelty. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

  • Barber, B., & Fox, R. C. (1958). The case of the floppy-eared rabbits: An instance of serendipity gained and serendipity lost. American Journal of Sociology, 64(2), 128–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, A. A., Hawkins, M. F., & López-Muñoz, F. (2010). Toward standardized usage of the word serendipity in the historiography of psychopharmacology. Journal of the History of the Neurosciences, 19, 253–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedessem, B. & Ruphy, S. (2016). Serendipity: An argument for scientific freedom? Presented to the Philosophy of Science Association, Atlanta (November). http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/12508/. Accessed 14 July 2017.

  • Boyer, T. (2014). Is a bird in the hand worth two in the bush? Or, whether scientists should publish intermediate results. Synthese, 191, 17–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bush, V. (1945). Science: The endless frontier. Washington DC: United States Government Printing Office.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2006). Strong and weak emergence. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (Eds.), The re-emergence of emergence (pp. 244–254). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, P. (2006). Conceptual foundations of emergence theory. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (Eds.), The re-emergence of emergence (pp. 1–31). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copeland, S. M. (2015). The case of the triggered memory: Serendipitous discovery and the ethics of clinical research. Dalhousie University (Ph.D. Thesis).

  • Cunha, M. P. E. (2005). Serendipity: Why some organizations are luckier than others. SSRN Electronic Journal. doi:10.2139/ssrn.882782.

  • Cunha, M. P. E., Clegg, S. R., & Mendonça, S. (2010). On serendipity and organizing. European Management Journal, 28, 319–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cunha, M. P., Rego, A., Clegg, S., & Lindsay, G. (2015). The dialectics of serendipity. European Management Journal, 33, 9–18.

  • Darbellay, F., Moody, Z., Sedooka, A., & Steffen, G. (2014). Interdisciplinary research boosted by serendipity. Creativity Research Journal, 26(1), 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Rond, M. & Morley, I. (2010). Introduction: Fortune and the prepared mind. In M. de Rond & I. Morley (Eds.), Serendipity: Fortune and the prepared mind (pp. 1–10). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • de Rond, M. (2014). The structure of serendipity. Culture and Organization, 20(5), 342–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diggins, F. W. E. (1999). The true history of the discovery of penicillin, with refutation of the misinformation in the literature. British Journal of Biomedical Science, 56, 83–93.

  • Erdelez, S. (1997). Information encountering: A conceptual framework for accidental information discovery. In ISIC ’96 Proceedings of an international conference on Information seeking in context (pp. 412–421). London, UK: Taylor Graham Publishing.

  • Estes, J. (2016). Serendipity: An ecologist’s quest to understand nature. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, G. A., & Deegan, J. G. (1996). Three principles of Serendip: Insight, chance, and discovery in qualitative research. Qualitative Studies in Education, 9(4), 434–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. (1979). Genesis and development of a scientific fact. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleming, S. A. (1945). Nobel lecture: Penicillin. Nobel Lectures, Physiology or Medicine, 1942–1962, 83–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster, A. E., & Ellis, D. (2014). Serendipity and its study. Journal of Documentation, 70(6), 1015–1038.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gest, H. (1997). Serendipity in scientific discovery: A closer look. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 41(1), 21–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbons, M. (2012). Reassessing discovery: Rosalind Franklin, scientific visualization, and the structure of DNA. Philosophy of Science, 79, 63–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heesen, R. (forthcoming). Communism and the incentive to share in science. Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1086/693875.

  • Kantorovich, A. (1993). Scientific discovery: Logic and tinkering. New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kefalidou, G., & Sharples, S. (2016). Encouraging serendipity in research: Designing technologies to support connection-making. International Journal of Human–Computer Studies, 89, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1990). The division of cognitive labor. The Journal of Philosophy, 87(1), 5–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koestler, A. (1964). The act of creation. London: Hutchinson & Co.

  • Kohn, A. (1989). Fortune or failure: Missed opportunities and chance discoveries in science. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawley, J. & Tompkins, P. (2008). Maximising serendipity?: The art of recognising and fostering potential. A systemic approach to change, resource document. http://www.cleanlanguage.co.uk/articles/articles/224/1/Maximising?Serendipity/Page1.html/print/224. Accessed 14 July 2017.

  • Liestman, D. (1992). Chance in the midst of design: Approaches to library research serendipity. RQ, 31(4), 524–532.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makri, S., & Blandford, A. (2012). Coming across information serendipitously—Part 1: A process model. Journal of Documentation, 68(5), 684–705.

  • McBirnie, A. (2008). Seeking serendipity: The paradox of control. Aslib Proceedings, 60(6), 600–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McBirnie, A., & Urquhart, C. (2011). Motifs: Dominant interaction patterns in event structures of serendipity. IR Information Research, 16(3). http://InformationR.net/ir/16-3/paper494.html. Accessed 5 Sept 2017.

  • McCay-Peet, L. & Toms, E. G. (2010). The process of serendipity in knowledge work. In Proceedings of the third symposium on information interaction in context (New Brunswick, NJ, USA) (pp. 377–381). doi:10.1145/1840784.1840842. Accessed 14 July 2017.

  • McCay-Peet, L. (2011). Exploring serendipity’s precipitating conditions. In P. Campos, N. Graham, J. Jorge, N. Nunes, P. Palanque, & M. Winckler (Eds.), Lecture notes in computer science: Human–computer interaction, INTERACT 2011, Lisbon, Portugal (pp. 398–401). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McCay-Peet, L., & Wells, P. (2017). Serendipity in the sciences: Exploring the boundaries. Proceedings of the Nova Scotian Institution of Science (PNSIS), 49(1), 97–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinnon, R. (2014). You make your own luck. Metaphilosophy, 45(4–5), 558–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. K. (1948). The bearing of empirical research upon the development of social theory. American Sociological Review, 13(5), 505–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. K., & Barber, E. (2004). The travels and adventures of serendipity: A study in sociological semantics and the sociology of science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michener, W. K., Bildstein, K. L., McKee, A., Parmenter, R. R., Hargrove, W. W., McClearn, D., et al. (2009). Biological field stations: Research legacies and sites for serendipity. Bioscience, 59(4), 300–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murayama, K., Nirei, M., & Shimizu, H. (2015). Management of science, serendipity, and research performance: Evidence from a survey of scientists in Japan and the U.S. Research Policy, 44, 862–873.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Napolitano, C. M. (2013). More than just a simple twist of fate: Serendipitous relations in developmental science. Human Development, 56(5), 291–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1997). Methods of discovery. Biology and Philosophy, 12, 127–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nutefall, J. E., & Ryder, P. M. (2010). The serendipitous research process. The Journal of Academic Librarianship, 36(3), 228–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. (1989). Serendipity: Accidental discoveries in science. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, V. L., Burkell, J., & Quan-Haase, A. (2011). Facets of serendipity in everyday chance encounters: A grounded theory approach to blog analysis. Information Research, 16(3), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Y. (2017). Temporal aspects of info-serendipity. Temporalités: Revue de sciences sociales et humaines. doi:10.4000/temporalites.3523.

  • Sommer, T. J. (2001). Suppression of scientific research: Bahramdipity and nulltiple scientific discoveries. Science and Engineering Ethics, 7(1), 77–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2003). The role of the priority rule in science. The Journal of Philosophy, 100(2), 55–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2017). Scientific sharing: Communism and the social contract. In T. Boyer-Kassem, C. May-Wilson & M. Weisberg (Eds.), Scientific collaboration and collective knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press. (forthcoming).

  • Taleb, N. N. (2007). The Black Swan: The impact of the highly improbable. New York City: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1998a). Ulcers and bacteria I?: Discovery and acceptance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biology and Biomedical Science, 29(1), 107–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1998b). Ulcers and bacteria II: Instruments, experiments, and social interactions. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 29(2), 317–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2002). Curing cancer? Patrick Lee’s path to the reovirus treatment. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 16(1), 79–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2012). Creative combinations of representations, scientific discovery and technological invention. In R. W. Proctor & E. J. Capaldi (Eds.), Psychology of science: Implicit and explicit processes. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Thagard, P., & Croft, D. (1999). Scientific discovery and technological innovation: Ulcers, dinosaur extinction, and the programming language Java. In L. Magnani, N. Nersessian, & P. Thagard (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in scientific discovery (pp. 125–137). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van Andel, P. (1994). Anatomy of the unsought finding. Serendipity: Origin, history, domains, traditions, appearances, patterns and programmability. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45(2), 631–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walpole, H. (1789). Letter to Mrs. More. In Private Correspondance of Horace Walpole (1820) (Vol. IV, p. 483). London: Rodwell and Martin.

  • Watson, J. & Crick, F. (1953). Molecular structure of nucleic acids-A structure for Deoxyribose Nucleic Acid. Nature, 4356(April 25), 737–738.

  • Watson, J. (2010). The double helix: A personal account of the discovery of the structure of DNA. W&N.

  • Weisburg, M., & Muldoon, R. (2009). Epistemic landscapes and the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy of Science, 76(2), 225–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to extend thanks to the CauseHealth team, my dissertation committee, the Dalhousie Philosophy Department colloquium, and various conference audiences for their constructive criticism and insightful questions. Two anonymous reviewers provided thoughtful advice on how to improve upon previous versions. Funding was provided by The Research Council of Norway (FRIPRO). The Research Council of Norway (NFR, FRIPRO scheme).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Samantha Copeland.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Copeland, S. On serendipity in science: discovery at the intersection of chance and wisdom. Synthese 196, 2385–2406 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1544-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1544-3

Keywords

Navigation