Skip to main content
Log in

Human nature and cognitive–developmental niche construction

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent theories in cognitive science have begun to focus on the active role of organisms in shaping their own environment, and the role of these environmental resources for cognition. Approaches such as situated, embedded, ecological, distributed and particularly extended cognition look beyond ‘what is inside your head’ to the old Gibsonian question of ‘what your head is inside of’ and with which it forms a wider whole—its internal and external cognitive niche. Since these views have been treated as a radical departure from the received view of cognition, their proponents have looked for support to similar extended views within (the philosophy of) biology, most notably the theory of niche construction. This paper argues that there is an even closer and more fruitful parallel with developmental systems theory and developmental niche construction. These ask not ‘what is inside the genes you inherited’, but ‘what the inherited genes are inside of’ and with which they form a wider whole—their internal and external ontogenetic niche, understood as the set of epigenetic, social, ecological, epistemic and symbolic legacies inherited by the organism as necessary developmental resources. To the cognizing agent, the epistemic niche presents itself not just as a partially self-engineered selective niche, as the niche construction paradigm will have it, but even more so as a partially self-engineered ontogenetic niche, a problem-solving resource and scaffold for individual development and learning. This move should be beneficial for coming to grips with our own (including cognitive) nature: what is most distinctive about humans is their developmentally plastic brains immersed into a well-engineered, cumulatively constructed cognitive–developmental niche.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is that reason that DST has only recently embraced the developmental niche construction paradigm (Stotz 2008; Stotz and Allen 2011).

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14(1), 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alberts, J. R. (2008). The nature of nurturant niches in ontogeny. Philosophical Psychology, 21(3), 295–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogin, B. (1997). Evolutionary hypotheses for human childhood. Yearbook of Physical Anthropology, 40, 63–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Champagne, F. A., & Curley, J. P. (2009). The transgenerational influence of maternal care on offspring gene expression and behavior in rodents. In D. Maestripieri & J. M. Mateo (Eds.), Maternal effects in mammals (pp. 182–202). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body and world together again. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs: Minds, technologies, and the future of human intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donald, M. (2000a). The central role of culture in cognitive evolution: A reflection on the myth of the “Isolated mind”. In L. Nucci, G. B. Saxe, & E. Turie (Eds.), Culture, thought and development (pp. 19–38). Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furth, H. G. (1987). Knowledge as desire: An essay on Freud and Piaget. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S. F. (2002). Genetic determinism: The battle between scientific data and social image in contemporary molecular biology. In A. Grunwald, M. Gutmann, & E. M. Neumann-Held (Eds.), On human nature: Anthropological, biological and philosophical foundations (pp. 121–140). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gluckman, P. D., & Hanson, M. A. (2006). Mismatch: Why our world no longer fits our bodies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gluckman, P. D., Hanson, M. A., & Beedle, A. S. (2007). Early life events and their consequences for later disease: a life history and evolutionary perspective. American Journal of Human Biology, 19(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E., & Gray, R. D. (1994). Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. Journal of Philosophy, XCI, 6, 277–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E., & Gray, R. D. (2004). The developmental systems perspective: Organism-environment systems as units of evolution. In K. Preston & M. Pigliucci (Eds.), The evolutionary biology of complex phenotypes (pp. 335–339). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E., & Stotz, K. (2000). How the mind grows: a developmental perspective on the biology of cognition. Synthese, 122(1–2), 29–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendriks-Jansen, H. (1996). Catching ourselves in the act: Situated activity, interactive emergence, evolution and human thought. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, E., Call, J., Hernandez-Lloreda, M. V., Hare, B., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Humans have evolved specialized skills of social cognition: the cultural intelligence hypothesis. Science, 317, 1360–1366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ingold, T. (1995). People like us: the concept of the anatomically modern human. Cultural Dynamics, 7(2), 187–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (2005). Evolution in four dimensions: Genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. Cambridge: The MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, J., & Feldman, M. W. (2000). Niche construction, biological evolution and cultural change. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23(1), 131–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamm, E., & Jablonka, E. (2008). The nurture of nature: hereditary plasticity in evolution. Philosophical Psychology, 21(3), 305–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Linquist, S., Machery, E., Griffiths, & P. E., Stotz, K. (2011). Exploring the folkbiological conception of behavioral development. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, (Evolution and human behavioural diversity).

  • Maestripieri, D. (2009). Maternal influences in offspring growth, reproduction, and behavior in primates. In D. Maestripieri & J. M. Mateo (Eds.), Maternal effects in mammals (pp. 256–291). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maestripieri, D., & Mateo, J. M. (Eds.). (2009a). Maternal effects in mammals. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maestripieri, D., & Mateo, J. M. (2009b). The role of maternal effects in mammalian evolution and adaptation. In D. Maestripieri & J. M. Mateo (Eds.), Maternal effects in mammals (pp. 1–10). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mateo, J. M. (2009). Maternal influences on development, social relationship, and survival behavior. In D. Maestripieri & J. M. Mateo (Eds.), Maternal effects in mammals (pp. 133–158). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meaney, M. J. (2001). Maternal care, gene expression, and the transmission of individual differences in stress reactivity across generations. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 24, 1161–1192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, C. L. (1984). Maternal contributions to the development of masculine sexual behavior in laboratory rats. Developmental Psychobiology, 17(4), 347–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mousseau, T. A., & Fox, C. W. (Eds.). (1998). Maternal effects as adaptations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nathanielsz, P. W., & Thornburg, K. L. (2003). Fetal programming: from gene to functional systems – an overview. Journal of Physiology, 547, 3–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, F. J. (1988). Niche-constructing phenotypes. In H. C. Plotkin (Ed.), The role of behavior in evolution (pp. 73–132). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley, M., & Stotz, K. (2011). Intervention, integration and translation in obesity research. Genetic, developmental and metaorganismal approaches. Philosophy, Ethics and Humanities in Medicine.

  • Oyama, S. (1985). The ontogeny of information: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S., Griffiths, P. E., & Gray, R. D. (2001). Introduction: What is developmental systems theory? In S. Oyama, P. E. Griffiths, & R. D. Gray (Eds.), Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Portmann, A. (1941). Die Tragzeiten der Primaten und die Dauer der Schwangerschaft beim Menschen: Ein Problem der vergleichenden Biologie. Revue Suisse de Zoologie, 48, 511–518.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2009). Extended cognition and the mark of the mental. Philosophical Psychology, 22(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. D. (2009). Cognitive systems and the extended mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sinha, C. (1988). Language and representation: A socio-naturalistic approach to human development. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinha, C. (1989). Evolution, development and the social production of mind. Cultural Dynamics, 2(2), 188–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2003). Thought in a hostile world: The evolution of human cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2004). Externalism, epistemic artefacts and the extended mind. In R. Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge. New studies on cognition and intentionality (pp. 239–254). Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Sex and death: An introduction to the philosophy of biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K. (1996). The psychology of knowledge in the context of evolutionary theory: reflections on the link between cognition and sociability. Evolution and Cognition, 2(1), 22–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K. (2006). Molecular epigenesis: distributed specificity as a break in the central dogma’. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 28(4), 527–544.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K. (2008). The ingredients for a postgenomic synthesis of nature and nurture. Philosophical Psychology, 21(3), 359–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K., & Allen, C. (2011). From cell-surface receptors to higher learning: A whole world of experience. In K. Plaisance & T. Reydon (Eds.), Philosophy of behavioural biology (Boston studies in philosophy of science). Boston: Springer.

  • Tomasello, M., & Call, J. (2004). The role of humans in the cognitive development of apes revisited. Animal Cognition, 7, 213–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West, M. J., & King, A. P. (1987). Settling nature and nurture into an ontogenetic niche. Developmental Psychobiology, 20(5), 549–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West, M. J., & King, A. P. (2008). Deconstructing innate illusions: reflections on nature-nurture-niche from an unlikely source. Philosophical Psychology, 21(3), 383–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West, M. J., King, A. P., & Arberg, A. A. (1988). The inheritance of niches. In E. M. Blass (Ed.), Handbook of behavioral neurobiology. New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: The next step. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M., & Clark, A. (1999). Genic representation: reconciling content and causal complexity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50(1), 103–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The individual in the fragile sciences—cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., & Clark, A. (2009). How to situate cognition: Letting nature take its course. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 55–77). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

This research was supported under Australian Research Council's Discovery Projects funding scheme (project number 0878650). This paper benefited from comments from the audience of a workshop at Wollongong University, ‘Embodied Cognition, Enactivism and the Extended Mind’, and from discussions with Richard Menary and Paul Griffiths.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Karola Stotz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Stotz, K. Human nature and cognitive–developmental niche construction. Phenom Cogn Sci 9, 483–501 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-010-9178-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-010-9178-7

Keywords

Navigation