Skip to main content
Log in

Minds: extended or scaffolded?

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper discusses two perspectives, each of which recognises the importance of environmental resources in enhancing and amplifying our cognitive capacity. One is the Clark–Chalmers model, extended further by Clark and others. The other derives from niche construction models of evolution, models which emphasise the role of active agency in enhancing the adaptive fit between agent and world. In the human case, much niche construction is epistemic: making cognitive tools and assembling other informational resources that support and scaffold intelligent action. I shall argue that extended mind cases are limiting cases of environmental scaffolding, and while the extended mind picture is not false, the niche construction model is a more helpful framework for understanding human action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The beyond-the-body conception of the mind goes by many other names: “vehicle externalism”; “active externalism” and “locational externalism”. I shall for simplicity use the “extended mind” terminology; I think it was the first used explicitly for this position and is the most widely recognised terminology. See, for example, (Clark 2007, 2008; Clark and Chambers 1998; Dennett 2000; Menary 2010; Sutton 2006; Sterelny 2010; Wilson 1994).

  2. Mark Rowlands has defended the view that there could be external digestion, but he has in mind much more recondite cases, in which processing that is normally managed by internal mechanisms depends instead on prosthetic devices (Rowlands 2009).

  3. Thus, they require that both the resource itself and its informational content be reliably accessed and at low cost and that, as a default, the agent unreflectively trusts the source.

  4. Here Clark has clearly forgotten his Wallace; Chalmers is an unreconstructed Cartesian if ever there was one.

  5. John Sutton also develops a dimensional analysis of environmental resources, but his dimensions are differences in material substrate rather than in functional relations between agent and resource. Thus, he distinguishes between artefacts, the use of other agents and the reliance on stable features of the physical environment (Sutton 2006).

  6. I was alerted to this idea in Malafouris (2008), but I have learned from Richard Menary that it dates back to Mearleau-Ponty and that it has been defended in some detail in Gallagher (2005).

  7. Of course it is possible to suggest that there is a collective agent, the cast itself, that knows the script and in virtue of this array of environmental resources. But while there may be a collective agent, there are also individual agents, each of whom knows his part, though only in context and with the aid of various forms of support. Little of that can be regarded as part of an agent’s cognitive system, inter alia, because agents would have to be part of one another. Mark Rowlands, in distinguishing external components of the mind from mere resources, appeals to an intuitive notion of “belonging to” an agent (Rowlands 2009). None of the crucial resources here intuitively belongs to any specific agent.

  8. This paper benefited greatly from generous feedback from three audiences. These were the 2009 New Zealand Division of the Australasian Association of Philosophy Conference in Palmerston North; Embodied Cognition, Enactivism and the Extended Mind (a Wollongong workshop) and the ANU philsoc.

References

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2007). Curing cognitive hiccups: A defense of the extended mind. Journal of Philosophy, 104(4), 163–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2010). Memento’s revenge: The exended mind extended. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chambers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1982). The extended phenotype. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (2004). Extended phenotype—but not too extended. A reply to Laland, Turner and Jablonka. Biology and Philosophy, 19, 377–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (1997). The symbolic species: The co-evolution of language and the brain. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2000). Making tools for thinking. In D. Sperber (Ed.), Metarepresentation: A multidisciplinary perspective (pp. 17–29). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R., & Gamble, C. (2009). The ecology of social transitions in human evolution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 364, 3267–3279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurven, M., & Hill, K. (2009). Why do men hunt? A reevaluation of “man the hunter” and the sexual division of labor. Current Anthropology, 50(1), 51–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, K., & Kaplan, H. (1999). Life history traits in humans: Theory and empirical studies. Annual Review of Anthropology, 28, 397–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K. (2004). Extending the extended phenotype. Biology and Philosophy, 19(3), 313–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K. (2007). Niche construction, human behavioural ecology and evolutionary psychology. In R. Dunbar & L. Barrett (Eds.), Oxford handbook of evolutionary psychology (pp. 35–48). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, J., & Feldman, M. (2000). Niche construction, biological evolution and cultural change. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 131–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2008). Beads for a plastic mind: The ‘blind man’s stick’ (BMS) hypothesis and the active nature of material culture. Cambridge Archaeological Journal, 18(3), 401–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2010). The extended mind and cognitive integration. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connell, J. F., Hawkes, K., & Jones, N. B. (1999). Grandmothering and the evolution of Homo erectus. Journal of Human Evolution, 36(5), 461–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, J., Laland, K., & Feldman, M. (2003). Niche construction: The neglected process in evolution., monographs in population biology. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2009). Extended cognition and the mark of the mental. Philosophical Psychology, 22(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Serventy, V. (Ed.). (1982). The wrens and warblers of Australia, National Photographic Index of Australian Wildlife. Sydney: Angus and Robinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2003). Thought in a hostile world. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2004). Externalism, epistemic artefacts and the extended mind. In R. Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge. New studies on cognition and intentionality (pp. 239–254). Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2006). Cognitive load and human decision, or, three ways of rolling the rock up hill. In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind: Volume 2: culture and cognition (pp. 218–233). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2007). Social intelligence, human intelligence and niche construction. Proceedings of the Royal Society London (series B), 362(1480), 719–730.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2009). Novelty, plasticity and niche construction: The influence of phenotypic variation on evolution. In A. Barberousse, M. Morange, & T. Pradeu (Eds.), Mapping the future of biology. Evolving concepts and theories. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2010). From hominins to humans: How sapiens became behaviourally modern. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, London, B, in press.

  • Stout, D. (2002). Skill and cognition in stone tool production: An ethnographic case study from Irian Jaya. Current Anthropology, 43(5), 693–722.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2006). Distributed cognition: Domains and dimensions. Pragmatics & Cognition, 14(2), 235–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2010). Exograms, interdisciplinarity and the cognitive life of things. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tribble, E. (2005). Distributing cognition in the globe. Shakespeare Quarterly, 56(2), 135–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2004). Is language the ultimate artefact? Language Science, 26(6), 693–715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiten, A., McGuigan, N., Marshall-Pescini, S., & Hopper, L. M. (2009). Emulation, imitation, over-imitation and the scope of culture for child and chimpanzee. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, series B, 364(1528), 2417–2428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiten, A., Schick, K., & Toth, N. (2009). The evolution and cultural transmission of percussive technology: Integrating evidence from palaeoanthropology and primatology. Journal of Human Evolution, 30, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (1994). Wide computationalism. Mind, 103, 351–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wrangham, R. W. (2001). Out of the pan, into the fire: How our ancestors’ evolution depended on what they ate. In F. de Waal (Ed.), Tree of life (pp. 121–143). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wrangham, R. (2009). Catching fire: How cooking made us human. London: Profile.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wrangham, R., Jones, J., Laden, G., Pilbeam, D., & Conklin-Brittain, N. (1999). The raw and the stolen: Cooking and the ecology of human origins. Current Anthropology, 40(5), 567–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kim Sterelny.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sterelny, K. Minds: extended or scaffolded?. Phenom Cogn Sci 9, 465–481 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-010-9174-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-010-9174-y

Keywords

Navigation