Skip to main content
Log in

Participatory sense-making

An enactive approach to social cognition

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

As yet, there is no enactive account of social cognition. This paper extends the enactive concept of sense-making into the social domain. It takes as its departure point the process of interaction between individuals in a social encounter. It is a well-established finding that individuals can and generally do coordinate their movements and utterances in such situations. We argue that the interaction process can take on a form of autonomy. This allows us to reframe the problem of social cognition as that of how meaning is generated and transformed in the interplay between the unfolding interaction process and the individuals engaged in it. The notion of sense-making in this realm becomes participatory sense-making. The onus of social understanding thus moves away from strictly the individual only.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We must acknowledge here that by autonomy of the interactors we should understand a possibly multi-dimensional complex of identities that co-exist in what we call a subject, from his physical body, his sensorimotor integration, his function in the interaction, to his broader contextual, relational and historical roles. Complex interactions may result in the loss of the autonomy associated with a specific identity but they are still social as long as other autonomous identities remain in interaction (e.g., a conversation where an employee loses his job is a definitive blow to the sustained identity of the employee as such, but not to the social agent that still enjoys his autonomy to express his reaction to the situation). We expect that even though the proposed distinction holds in general (encounters are not social if an interactor’s autonomy is lost), specific instances must be unpacked carefully in terms of what identities are at play in what we have loosely termed an interactor.

  2. Participatory sense-making is not restricted to human social interactions. Many social animals build up coherences of significance by engaging in coordinated displays, such as circle-walking in wolves where potential contenders size each other up by making turns around each other (Moran et al. 1981), their intention to fight or not being affected by the emergent coordination. Even in simple models in evolutionary robotics the discrimination between different significant contexts can be performed through appropriate coordination between individuals (Di Paolo, Rohde and De Jaegher 2007; Quinn 2001). Recent work modelling the detection of social contingency in minimal agents shows in explicit terms how individual perception alters its meaning as a result of social coordination (Di Paolo, Rohde and Iizuka 2007).

References

  • Auvray, M., Lenay, C., & Stewart, J. (2006). The attribution of intentionality in a simulated environment: The case of minimalist devices. In Tenth Meeting of the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness. Oxford, UK.

  • Boden, M. (2006). Of islands and interactions. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13, 53–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (1990). The logic of practice. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buck, J., & Buck, E. (1976). Synchronous fireflies. Scientific American, 234, 74–85 (May).

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2007). Enactive appraisal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, (This issue).

  • Condon, W. S., & Ogston, W. D. (1971). Speech and body motion synchrony of the speaker–hearer. In D. L. Horton, & J. J. Jenkins (Eds.) The perception of language. Columbus, Ohio: Charles E. Merril Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, J. E. (1991). Correlated activity in the CNS: A role on every timescale? Trends in Neurosciences, 14, 397–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowley, S. (2007). How human infants deal with symbol grounding. Interaction Studies, 8, 81–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (2007). Narrative frameworks. In D. D. Hutto (Ed.) Narrative and understanding persons: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 60 (pp. 17–42). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H. (2006). Social interaction rhythm and participatory sense-making: An embodied, interactional approach to social understanding, with implications for autism, D.Phil. Thesis. In University of Sussex, Brighton, UK.

  • de Vignemont, F., & Singer, T. (2006). The empathic brain: How, when and why? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 435–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 97–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2007). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo, (Eds.), Enaction: towards a new paradigm for cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & Iizuka, H. (2007). Sensitivity to social contingency or stability of interaction? Modelling the dynamics of perceptual crossing. New Ideas in Psychology.

  • Fogel, A. (1993). Developing through relationships: Origins of communication, self and culture. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (1997). Mutual enlightenment: Recent phenomenology and cognitive science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4, 195–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: Theory, simulation or primary interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2004). Understanding interpersonal problems in autism: Interaction Theory as an alternative to Theory of Mind. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 11, 199–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2007). Logical and phenomenological arguments against simulation theory. In D. D. Hutto & M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Minding our practice: Folk psychology re-assessed. Springer.

  • Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., et al. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119, 593–609.

    Google Scholar 

  • Georgieff, N., & Jeannerod, M. (1998). Beyond consciousness of external events: A ‘who’ system for consciousness of action and self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 7, 465–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gill, S. P., Kawamori, M., Katagiri, Y., et al. (2000). Role of Body Moves in dialogue. International Journal of Language and Communication, 12, 89–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, E. (1972). Interaction ritual: Essays on face-to-face behavior. London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, E. (1983). The interaction order. American Sociological Review, 48, 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Granic, I. (2000). The self-organization of parent-child relations: Beyond bidirectional models. In M. D. Lewis, & I. Granic (Eds.) Emotion, development, and self-organization. Dynamic systems approaches to emotional development (pp. 267–297). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haken, H., & Köpchen, H. P. (1991). Rhythms in physiological systems. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, R. P. (2002). The cradle of thought. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2004). The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. Mind and Language, 19, 548–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2007). The narrative practice hypothesis: Origins and applications of Folk Psychology. In D. D. Hutto (Ed.), Narrative and understanding persons. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement: Cambridge University Press.

  • Jaffe, J., Beebe, B., & Feldstein, S., et al. (2001). Rhythms of dialogue in infancy: Coordinated timing in development. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaffe, J., & Feldstein, S. (1970). Rhythms of dialogue. London: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life. Toward a philosophical biology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self-organization of brain and behaviour. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendon, A. (1990). Conducting interaction: patterns of behavior in focused encounters. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klin, A., Jones, W., Schultz, R., et al. (2003). The enactive mind, or from actions to cognition: Lessons from autism. Philosophical Transactions of The Royal Society London B, 358, 345–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuramoto, Y. (1984). Chemical oscillations, waves and turbulence. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, G., Fentress, J. C., & Golani, I. (1981). A description of relational patterns of movement during “ritualized fighting” in wolves. Animal Behavior, 29, 1146–1165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, A., & Etxeberria, A. (2005). Agency in natural and artificial systems. Artificial Life, 11, 161–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, L., & Trevarthen, C. (1985). Emotional regulation of interactions between 2-month-olds and their mothers. In T. M. Field, & N. A. Fox (Eds.) Social perception in infants (pp. 177–197). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myin, E. (2003). An account of color without a subject? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 42–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, M. J., & Garrod, S. (2004). Toward a mechanistic psychology of dialogue. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27,169–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Port, R. F., & van Gelder, T. (Eds.) (1995). Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Quinn, M. (2001). Evolving communication without dedicated communication channels. In Advances in artificial life: Sixth European Conference on Artificial Life (ECAL 2001). Prague: Springer pp. 357–366.

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2007). Rethinking commonsense psychology: A critique of folk psychology, theory of mind and simulation. Hampshire/New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruhleder, K., & Jordan, B. (2001). Co-constructing non-mutual realities: Delay-generated trouble in distributed interaction. Journal of Computer Supported Cooperative Work, 10, 113–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, H. (1992). Lectures on conversation volumes I and II. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, H., Schegloff, E. A., & Jefferson, G. (1974). A simplest systematics for the organization of turn-taking for conversation. Language, 50, 696–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffrin, D. (1994). Approaches to discourse. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, R. C., & O'Brien, B. (1997). Evaluating the dynamics of unintended interpersonal coordination. Ecological Psychology, 9, 189–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanker, S., & King, B. J. (2002). The emergence of a new paradigm in ape language research. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 605–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (1999). Emotion and movement: A beginning empirical-phenomenological analysis of their relationship. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6, 259–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, D. (2002/1977). The first relationship: Infant and mother. London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2001). Empathy and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2005). Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 407–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press.

  • Thompson, E., & Varela, F. J. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 418–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thorpe, W. H. (1972). Duetting and antiphonal song in birds: Its extent and significance. Leiden: E. J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torrance, S. (2005). In search of the enactive: Introduction to special issue on enactive experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 357–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. (1979). Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (Ed.) Before speech (pp. 321–347). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tronick, E. (2005). Why is connection with others so critical? The formation of dyadic states of consciousness and the expansion of individuals’ states of consciousness: Coherence governed selection and the co-creation of meaning out of messy meaning making. In J. Nadel, & D. Muir (Eds.) Emotional development (pp. 293–316). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tronick, E. Z., Als, H., & Adamson, L. (1979). Structure of early face-to-face communicative interactions. In M. Bullowa (Ed.) Before speech (pp. 349–370). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1999). Wooden iron? Husserlian phenomenology meets cognitive science. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.) Naturalizing phenomenology (pp. 245–265). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1979). Principles of biological autonomy. New York: Elsevier (North Holland).

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1991). Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In A. Tauber (Ed.) Organism and the origin of self pp. 79–107. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3, 330–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1997). Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition, 34, 72–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1999). The specious present: A neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.) Naturalizing phenomenology (pp. 266–314). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winfree, A. T. (2001). The geometry of biological time. London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Stephen Cowley, Marek McGann and Steve Torrance for their very helpful comments on this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hanne De Jaegher.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E. Participatory sense-making. Phenom Cogn Sci 6, 485–507 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9

Keywords

Navigation