Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Moral implications of obstetric technologies for pregnancy and motherhood

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Drawing on sociological and anthropological studies, the aim of this article is to reconstruct how obstetric technologies contribute to a moral conception of pregnancy and motherhood, and to evaluate that conception from a normative point of view. Obstetrics and midwifery, so the assumption, are value-laden, value-producing and value-reproducing practices, values that shape the social perception of what it means to be a “good” pregnant woman and to be a “good” (future) mother. Activities in the medical field of reproduction contribute to “kinning”, that is the making of particular social relationships marked by closeness and special moral obligations. Three technologies, which belong to standard procedures in prenatal care in postmodern societies, are presently investigated: (1) informed consent in prenatal care, (2) obstetric sonogram, and (3) birth plan. Their widespread application is supposed to serve the moral (and legal) goal of effecting patient autonomy (and patient right). A reconstruction of the actual moral implications of these technologies, however, reveals that this goal is missed in multiple ways. Informed consent situations are marked by involuntariness and blindness to social dimensions of decision-making; obstetric sonograms construct moral subjectivity and agency in a way that attribute inconsistent and unreasonable moral responsibilities to the pregnant woman; and birth plans obscure the need for a healthcare environment that reflects a shared-decision-making model, rather than a rational-choice-framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Sonogram enables also the future father to make visual contact with the fetus. Since the fetus is constituted as a subject separated from the woman and as a being in need of protection, the future father might feel more involved and responsible for the well-being of the fetus. This is a novel situation because it facilitates the possibility of a felt engagement of the future father with the fetus. However, there still exist double standards for “responsible parenting” and “duty to assist” for the man and the woman, especially in the USA where court-ordered caesarian deliveries are known, but no court-ordered duty exists for a father, e.g. to donate a rein to his child (Little 1996: 395).

  2. This fits well to a “risk society” (Beck 1986), “a modern culture characterized by pervasive anxiety about and efforts to ´colonize´ the future (Giddens 1991) […] ‘so risks are a kind of virtual, yet real, reality’ (Beck 1998: 11)” (Wolf 2007: 612).

  3. There are certainly limits to flexibility here. The Obstetrics and Gynecology Risk Research Group convincingly argues, for instance, that cesarean delivery on maternal request would not ultimately serve the goal of ensuring autonomy to laboring women (Kukla et al. 2009; Little et al. 2008; Lyerly et al. 2007, 2009; Lyerly and Little 2010). Their argument is that such requests would lead to shifting cultural norms and medical standards towards cesarean, so that ultimately it would become harder to facilitate vaginal deliveries (Little et al. 2008). Such a medical mode of child birth would also give way to a normalization of child birth as a surgical process in spite of better knowledge about health risks associated with surgical delivery (Bergeron 2007; Mander 2007; Nilstun et al. 2008). Obstetric skills and knowledge would also be lost, e.g. for vaginal birth of fetus in breech presentation, if caesarians were more routinely performed. Because of these consequences the right to cesarean on demand is widely contested by ethicists.

  4. For trying to balance harms and benefits of ultrasound cf. McCullough and Chervenak (1994: 201–206).

References

  • Beck, Ulrich. 1986. Risikogesellschaft. Auf dem Weg in eine andere Moderne. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, Ulrich. 1998. Politics of risks society. In The politics of risk society, ed. J. Franklin, 9–22. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergeron, Veronique. 2007. The ethics of cesarean section on maternal request: A feminist critique of the American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists’ position on patient choice surgery. Bioethics 9: 478–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bister, Milena. 2010. Soziale Praktiken des Einwilligens: Informed Consent-Verfahren und biomedizinische Forschung im Krankenhauskontext. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Vienna, Vienna.

  • Brakman, Sarah-Vaughn. 2006. Adoption, ART and a Re-Conception of the maternal Body: Toward embodied Maternity. Hypatia 1: 54–73.

  • Burkart, G. 2002. Entscheidungen zur Elternschaft revisited. Was leistet der Entscheidungsbegriff für biographische Übergänge. In Elterschaft heute: Gesellschaftliche Rahmenbedingungen und individuelle Gestaltungsaufgaben, eds. N.F. Schneider and H. Matthias-Bleck, 23–48. Opladen: Leske und Budrich.

  • Callahan, Joan. 1995. Reproduction, ethics and the LAW. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlton, Troy, et al. 2005. Decision making in laboring women ethical issues for perinatal nurses. Journal of Perinatal and Neonatal Nursing 2: 145–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chan, S. and Harris, J. 2008. Enhancement is good for you!: Understanding the ethics of genetic enhancement. Gene Therapy 15(5): 338–339.

  • Christman, John. 2004. Relational autonomy, liberal individualism and the social constitution of the selves. Philosophical Studies 1–2: 143–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, John. 2008. Selecting potential Children and unconditional parental Love. Bioethics 5: 258–268.

  • Downe, Soo. 2004. Risk and normality in the maternity service. In Ethics and midwifery, ed. L. Frith and H. Draper, 2nd ed. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science.

  • Duden, B. 2002. Frauen ohne gute Hoffnung (Interview). In Vom Stammbaum zur Stammzelle: Reproduktionsmedizin, Pränataldiagnostik und menschlicher Rohstoff, ed. E.  Brähler et.al., 307–319. Gießen: Psychosozial-Verlag.

  • Dworkin, Gerald. 1981. Taking risks, assessing responsibility. Hasting Center Report 11: 26–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faden, R., et al. 1986. A histrory and theory of informed consent. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Finkler, Kaja. 2001. The kin in the gene: The medicalization of family and kinship in American Society. Current Anthropology 2: 235–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • García, E., et al. 2009. Reconsidering prenatal screening: An empirical–ethical approach to understand moral dilemmas as a question of personal preferences. Journal of Medical Ethics 7: 410–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • García, E., et al. 2011. Women´s view on the moral staus of nature in the context of prenatal screening decisions. Journal of Medical Ethics 37: 461–465.

  • Giddens, Anthony. 1991. Modernity and self-identity. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Goering, Sara. 2009. Postnatal reproductive autonomy: Promoting relational autonomy and self-trust in new parents. Bioethics 23(1): 9–19.

  • Hauke, Kai, and Dippong, Natalie. 2011. Legitimationsprobleme moderner Geburtsmedizin. In Ethik in der Medizin. Published online: 11 June 2011.

  • Hauser-Schäublin, Brigitta. 2010. Manipulierte Substanzen, rekonfigurierte Verwandtschaften: Humantechnologische Prozesse und ihre Bedeutung für Verwandtschaft zwischen Normativität und Flexibilität. In Verwandtschaft heute, Positionen, Ergebnisse und Perspektiven, ed. E. Alber et al., 249–277. Berlin: Dietrich Reimer Verlag.

  • Hogle, L.F. 2007. Emerging Medical Technologies section. In The handbook of science and technology studies, 841–874. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

  • Katz Rothman, B. 1986. The tentative pregnancy: Prenatal diagnosis and the future of motherhood. New York: Penguin Books.

  • Kingdon, C., et al. 2009. Choice and birth method: Mixed-method study of caesarean delivery for maternal request. BJOG 7: 886–895.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kneuper, Elsbeth. 2005. Mutterwerden in Deutschland: Eine ethnologische Studie. Münster: LIT-Verlag.

  • Kukla, Rebecca. 2006. Ethics and ideology in breastfeeding advocacy campaigns. Hypatia 1: 157–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, Rebecca. 2005. Mass hysteria: Medicine, culture and mothers’ bodies. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

  • Kukla, Rebecca et al. 2009. Finding autonomy in birth. Bioethics 23(1): 1–8.

  • Laslie, Adele E. 1982. Ethical issues in childbirth. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 7: 179–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, Amy Su May, and Maggie Kirkman. 2008. Disciplinary discourses: Rates of caesarean section explained by medicine, midwifery and feminism. Health Care for Women International 5: S448–S467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Little, Margaret Olivia. 1996. Procreative liberty, biological connections and motherhood. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6(4): 392–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Little, Margaret Olivia, et al. 2008. Mode of delivery: Towards responsible inclusion of patient preferences. Obstetrics and Gynecology 112: 913–918.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyerly, A.D. 2006. Shame, gender, birth. Hypatia 1: 101–118.

  • Lyerly, A.D. et al. 2007. Risk, value and decision-making around pregnancy. Obstetrics and Gynecology 109: 979–984.

  • Lyerly, A.D., et al. 2009. Risk and the pregnant body. Hastings Center Report 39(6): 34–42.

  • Lyerly, A.D. and Little, M.A. 2010. Toward an ethically responsible approach to vaginal birth after caesarean. Seminars in Perinatology 5: 337–344.

  • Mackenzie, Catrina. 2008. Relational autonmy, normative authority and perfectionism. Journal of social Philosophy 4: 512–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maier, Barbara. 2000. Ethik in Gynäkologie und Geburtshilfe. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mander, Rosemary. 2007. Caesarean: Just another way of birth?. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCullough, Laurence B., and Chervenak, Frank A. 1994. Ethics in obstetrics and gynecology. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • McDougall, Rosalind. 2007. Parental virtue: A new way of thinking about the morality of reproductive actions. Bioethics 4: 181–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLeod, C. 2002. Self-Trust and Reproductive Autonomy. Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press.

  • Nilstun, Tore, et al. 2008. Caesarean delivery on maternal request: Can the ethical problem be solved by the principlist approach? BMC Medical Ethics 9: 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rapp, Rayna. 1997. Real-time fetus: the role of sonogram in the age of monitored reproduction. In Anthropological interventions in emerging sciences and technologies, ed. Gary Lee Downey, and Joseph Dumit, 31–48. Santa Fe: Cyborgs & Citadels.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapp, Rayna. 1998. Refusing prenatal diagnosis: The meanings of bioscience in a multicultural world. Science, Technology and Human Values 23: 45–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samerski, Silja. 2002. Die verrechnete Hoffnung: Von der selbstbestimmten Entscheidung durch genetische Beratung. Münster: LIT-Verlag.

  • Schnegg, M., et al. 2010. Verwandtschaft heute: Positonen, Ergebnisse und Forschungsperspektiven. In Verwandtschaft heute, Positionen, Ergebnisse und Perspektiven, ed. E. Alber et al., 7–44. Berlin: Dietrich Reimer Verlag.

  • Seavilleklein, V. 2008. The Values and Practice of Prenatal Screening in Canada. Canadian theses, Dalhousie University, Halifax.

  • Simmonds, A., and Peter, E. 2007. Understanding the everyday moral practices of midwifes and intrapartum nurses. The Canadian Journal of Nursing Research 4: 117–129.

  • Sismondo, S. 2004. An Introduction to Science and Technology Studies. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Smeenk, A.D.J., et al. 2003. Medicalisation and obstetric care: An analysis of developments in Dutch midwifery. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2: 153–165.

  • Spoel, Philippa. 2006. Midwifery, Consumerism and the Ethics of Informed Choice. In Bordering Biomedicine: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Health, Illness and Disease, eds. L. Twohig and V. Kalitzkus, 198–213. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

  • Stone, Linda. 2003. Introduction to contemporary directions in kinship. In Kinship and family: An anthropological Reader, eds. Robert J. Parkin and Linda Stone, 331–341. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Thompson, Faye E. 2003. The practise setting: Site of ethical conflict for some mothers and midwives. Nursing Ethics 6: 588–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van den Daele, Wolfgang. 1988. Der Fötus als Subjekt und die Autonomie der Frau. Wissenschaftlich-technische Optionen und soziale Kontrollen in der Schwangerschaft. In Frauensituation: Veränderungen in den letzten 20 Jahren, ed. Uta Gerhardt and Yvonne Schütze, 189–215. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.

  • Verbeek, Peter-Paul. 2008. Obstetric ultrasound and the technological mediation of morality: A postphenomenological analysis. Human Studies 1: 11–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldby, Catherine. 2002. Stem cells, tissue cultures and the production of biovalue. Health 6(3): 305–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westlund, Andrea C. 2009. Rethinking relational autonomy. Hypatia 4: 26–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris Marion. 1984. Pregnant embodiment: Subjectivity and alienation. Journal of Medical Medicine and Philosophy 9: 45–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Ethical standard

This study was funded by Lichtenberg-Kolleg: The Göttingen Institute for Advanced Study in the Humanities & Social Sciences, University of Goettingen, Germany (Fellow-in-Residence 2011). This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Susanne Brauer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Brauer, S. Moral implications of obstetric technologies for pregnancy and motherhood. Med Health Care and Philos 19, 45–54 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-015-9635-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-015-9635-8

Keywords

Navigation