Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Rational Choice, Agency and Thoughtfully Reflective Decision Making: The Short and Long-Term Consequences of Making Good Choices

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Quantitative Criminology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Notions of human agency are a prominent part of some but not all criminological theories. For example, McCarthy (Annu Rev Sociol 28:417–442, 2002) argues that rational choice theory, which allows persons great involvement in decision making, is more congenial with notions of human agency than others. It would appear from his argument that rational choice theory offers fertile ground to develop a clearly defined role for human agency in criminal behavior. In this paper we have taken up McCarthy’s view and argue that an important part of what is human agency consists of thoughtfully reflective decision making. We outline four elements of thoughtfully reflective decision making, and claim that it is a characteristic that varies both across persons and within persons over time. It is in short the process by which good decisions are made because by using this process one increases the likelihood that choices made will be consistent with preferences. We develop a clear operational definition of thoughtfully reflective decision making and link it to the concept of human agency. We also articulate testable hypotheses about the short-term and longer-term implications of thoughtfully reflective decision making. We conclude with a discussion of what we think lies ahead for future conceptual and empirical work.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The idea that there is an individual-level attribute that captures differences in the process through which decisions are made and life is approached is certainly not new. There is an abundant literature in philosophy, psychology, and sociology about good or competent decision making (Baron 2008; Byrnes 1998, 2002; Rescher 2003). Clausen (1991, 1993) describes planful competence as self-knowledge about one’s abilities and interests and how to take advantage of them, and the self-confidence to undertake such action. The three components of planful competence are dependability, intellectual involvement, and self-confidence. Those who are planfully competent are predicted to have more favorable long-term life outcomes such as stable work careers and more successful marriages. Langer (1989) describes mindfulness as the ability to think openly and creatively about problems and how to solve them. Its opposite, mindlessness, is characterized by rigid thinking and an inability to think out of context. Like planful competence, those possessing mindfulness are predicted to make better decisions and enjoy a wealth of better short- and long-term life outcomes. What we have called thoughtfully reflective decision making is different than both planful competence and mindfulness. Competence is based more upon one’s abilities and capacities such as intelligence, confidence, and punctuality while mindfulness refers more to the ability to think creatively or “out of the box”—the ability to see novel solutions. TRDM, though cognitive, is not determined by intelligence but is more multidimensional, including as it does a complex of abilities and traits such as emotional maturity, and motivation. Those who make thoughtfully reflective decisions, then, combine several personal competencies as well as the ability to reconcile emotions, competing situational and motivational demands that may interfere with good decision making (see Byrnes et al. 1999; Byrnes 2002).

  2. For example, what is the answer to the following question. “A bat and a ball cost $1.10 in total. The bat costs $1 more than the ball. How much does the ball cost?” (Kahneman 2003: 1450). An intuitive answer would be 10¢ because it is easy to think that a dollar more than that is the desired total cost of $1.00, but it would be wrong because if the bat costs $1 more than the ball then the bat must cost $1.10, and the total cost would be $1.20 while the total must be $1.10. The correct answer is 5¢ for the ball and $1.05 for the bat. Most of us might immediately say the ball costs 10¢ on the basis of quick intuition, but if asked to give careful thought to the problem before answering we would likely come up with the correct answer.

  3. Although we argue that TRDM varies across the life course we cannot directly test this hypothesis. In the Add Health data, measures of TRDM are only now available at the first wave. In a cross-section, however, TRDM does vary monotonically with age.

  4. For one exception see McGloin and Shermer (2009).

  5. An implication of this would be that unintended acts cannot be said to be the product of agency. When Laub and Sampson (2003), for example, refer to “desistance by default”—quitting crime without deliberating intending to or without one’s awareness—this is not by our understanding acting with agency.

  6. This third criterion excluded 12 additional respondents who were either 11, 20, or 21 years old at wave 1. These respondents were not age-normative for grades 7–12.

  7. One was added to each response so that the distribution began at one rather zero, and all values had a defined natural log.

  8. All respondents in the core sample were of voting age (at least 18 years old) on that date.

  9. This is calculated as 1−LL(model)/LL(null model) in a non-survey-adjusted model specification.

  10. Except that coefficients for ethnicity and the school fixed effects were omitted to conserve space.

References

  • Archer MS (2000) Being human: the problem of agency. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandura A (1989) Human agency in social cognitive theory. Am Psychol 44:1175–1184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandura A (2001) Social cognition theory: an agentic perspective. Annu Rev Psychol 52:1–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron J (2008) Thinking and deciding, 4th edn. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (1968) Crime and punishment: an economic approach. J Polit Econ 76:169–217

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (1993) Human capital: a theoretical and empirical analysis with special reference to education, 3rd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishai DM (2004) Does time preference change with age? J Popul Econ 17:583–602

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrnes JP (1998) The nature and development of decision making: a self-regulation model. Lawrence Erlbaum, Mahwah, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrnes JP (2002) The development of decision making. J Adolesc Health 31:208–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrnes JP, Miller DC, Reynolds M (1999) Learning to make good decisions: a self-regulation perspective. Child Dev 70:1121–1140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camic C (1986) The matter of habit. Am J Sociol 91:1039–1087

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll JS, Johnson EJ (1990) Decision research: a field guide. Sage Publications, Newbury Park, CA

    Google Scholar 

  • Clausen JA (1991) Adolescent competence and the shaping of the life course. Am J Sociol 96:805–842

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clausen JA (1993) American lives: looking back at children of the great depression. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman JS (1986) Social theory, social research, and a theory of action. Am J Sociol 91:1309–1335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman JS (1988) Social capital in the creation of human capital. Am J Sociol 94:S95–S120

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cornish DB, Clarke RV (1986) The reasoning criminal: rational choice perspectives on offending. Springer-Verlag, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • DiLisi M (2001) It’s all in the record: assessing self-control theory with an offender sample. Crim Just Rev 26:1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiMaggio P (1982) Cultural capital and school success: the impact of status culture participation on the grades of U.S. high school students. Am Sociol Rev 47:189–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emirbayer M, Mische A (1998) What is agency? Am J Sociol 103:962–1023

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni A (1988) The moral dimension: toward a new economics. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs S (2001) Beyond agency. Sociol Theor 19:24–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giordano PC, Cernkovich SA, Rudolph JL (2002) Gender, crime, and desistance: toward a theory of cognitive transformation. Am J Sociol 107:990–1064

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giordano PC, Cernkovich SA, Schroeder RD (2007) Emotions and crime over the life course: a neo-Median perspective on criminal continuity and change. Am J Sociol 112:1603–1661

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gogtay N, Giedd JN, Lusk L, Hayashi KM, Greenstein D, Vaituzis AC, Nugent TF, Herman DH, Clasen LS, Toga AW, Rapoport JL, Thompson PM (2004) Dynamic mapping of human cortical development during childhood through early adulthood. Proc Natl Acad Sci 101:8174–8179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottfredson M, Hirschi T (1990) A general theory of crime. Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottfredson MR (2006) The empirical status of control theory in criminology. In: Cullen FT, Wright JP, Blevins KR (eds) Taking stock: the status of criminological theory. Transaction, New Brunswick, NJ, pp 77–100

  • Grasmick HG, Tittle CR, Bursik RJ Jr (1993) Testing the core empirical implications of Gottfredson and Hirschi’s general theory of crime. J Res Crime Delinq 30:5–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green L, Fry AF, Myerson J (1994) Discounting of delayed rewards: a life-span comparison. Psychol Sci 5:33–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirschi T (2004) Self-control and crime. In: Baumeister RF, Vohs KD (eds) Handbook of self-regulation: research, theory and applications. Guilford Press, New York, pp 537–552

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitlin S, Elder GH Jr (2007) Time, self, and the curiously abstract concept of agency. Sociol Theory 25:170–191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffe O, Salazar C (2003) Aristotle. SUNY Press, Albany, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Junger M, West R, Timman R (2001) Crime and risky behavior in traffic: an example of cross-situational consistency. J Res Crime Delinq 38:439–459

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2003) Maps for bounded rationality: psychology for behavioral economics. Am Econ Rev 93:1449–1475

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keane C, Maxim P, Teevan J (1993) Drinking and driving, self-control, and gender: testing a general theory of crime. J Res Crime Delinq 30:30–46

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keckes J (1976) A justification of rationality. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiecolt KJ (1994) Stress and the decision to change oneself: a theoretical model. Soc Psychol Q 57:49–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langer EJ (1989) Mindfulness. Addison-Wesley, Reading, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Laub JH, Sampson RJ (2003) Shared beginnings, divergent lives: delinquent boys to age 70. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lilly RJ, Cullen FT, Ball RA (2006) Criminological theory. Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lochner L (2007) Individual perceptions of the criminal justice system. Am Econ Rev 97:444–460

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein G (1996) Out of control: visceral influences on behavior. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 65:272–292

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markus H, Nurius P (1986) Possible selves: the interface between motivation and the self-concept. In: Yardley K, Honess T (eds) Self and identity: psychological perspectives. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Markus H, Nurius P (1987) Possible selves. Am Psychol 41:954–969

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maruna S (2001) Making good: how ex-convicts reform and rebuild their lives. Washington, DC, American Psychological Association

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matsueda R, Kreager DA, Huizinga D (2006) Deterring delinquents: a rational choice model of theft and violence. Am Sociol Rev 71:95–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy B (2002) New economics of sociological criminology. Annu Rev Sociol 28:417–442

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGloin JM, Shermer LO (2009) Self-control and deviant peer structure. J Res Crime Delinq 46:35–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moffitt TE (1990) The neuropsychology of juvenile delinquency: a critical review of research and theory. In: Morris N, Tonry M (eds) Crime and justice: an annual review of research, vol 12. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan AB, Lilienfeld SO (2000) A meta-analytic review of the relation between antisocial behavior and neuropsychological measures of executive function. Clin Psychol Rev 20:113–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagin DS (2007) Moving choice to center stage in criminological research and theory. Criminology 45:259–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagin DS, Paternoster R (1994) Personal capital and social control: the deterrence implications of a theory of individual differences in offending. Criminology 32:581–606

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paternoster R, Saltzman LE, Waldo GP, Chiricos TG (1983) Estimating perceptual stability and deterrent effects: the role of perceived legal punishment in the inhibition of criminal involvement. J Crim Law Criminol 74:270–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piquero AR, Bouffard JA (2007) Something old, something new: a preliminary investigation of Hirschi’s redefined self-control. Just Q 24:1–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piquero AR, Moffitt TE (2005) Explaining the facts of crime: how the developmental taxonomy replies to Farrington’s invitation. In: Farrington DP (ed) Integrated developmental and life-course theories of offending. Transaction Books, New Brunswick, NJ, pp 51–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Plous S (1993) The psychology of judgment and decision making. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogarsky G, Piquero A (2003) Can punishment encourage offending? Investigating the “resetting effect”. J Res Crime Delinq 40:92–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogarsky G, Piquero AR, Paternoster R (2004) Modeling change in perceptions about sanction threats: the neglected linkage in deterrence theory. J Quant Criminol 20:343–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pratt T, Francis Cullen F (2000) The empirical status of Gottfredson and Hirschi’s general theory of crime: a meta-analysis. Criminology 38:931–964

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsay JR, Rostain AL (2008) Cognitive behavioral therapy for adult ADHD: an integrative psychosocial and medical approach. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Read D, Read NL (2004) Time discounting over the lifespan. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 94:22–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher N (2003) Sensible decisions: issues of rational decisions in personal choice and public policy. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Lanham, MD

    Google Scholar 

  • Shannahan MJ, Elder GH Jr (2002) History, agency and the life course. In: Dienstbier RA, Crockett LJ (eds) Agency, motivation, and the life course, vol 48. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln, NE, pp 145–186

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon H (1957) Models of man. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon H (1984) Models of bounded rationality, volume 1: economic analysis and public policy. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinberg L (2005) Cognitive and affective development in adolescence. Trends Cogn Sci 9:69–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2008) Nudge: improving decisions and health, wealth, and happiness. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner JH, Stets JE (2005) The sociology of emotions. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Vohs KD, Baumeister RF, Loewenstein G (2007) Do emotions help or hurt decision making? Russell Sage Foundation, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

We would like to thank Bill McCarthy, Jean McGloin, Alex Piquero and the anonymous reviewers for carefully reading the paper and offering many, many helpful suggestions. This research uses data from Add Health, a program project designed by J. Richard Udry, Peter S. Bearman, and Kathleen Mullan Harris, and funded by a grant P01-HD31921 from the Eunice Kennedy Shriver National Institute of Child Health and Human Development, with cooperative funding from 17 other agencies. Special acknowledgment is due Ronald R. Rindfuss and Barbara Entwisle for assistance in the original design. Persons interested in obtaining data files from Add Health should contact Add Health, Carolina Population Center, 123 W. Franklin Street, Chapel Hill, NC 27516-2524 (addhealth@unc.edu). No direct support was received from grant P01-HD31921 for this analysis.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Greg Pogarsky.

Appendix 1

Appendix 1

See Table 5

Table 5 Description and coding of variables

.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Paternoster, R., Pogarsky, G. Rational Choice, Agency and Thoughtfully Reflective Decision Making: The Short and Long-Term Consequences of Making Good Choices. J Quant Criminol 25, 103–127 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10940-009-9065-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10940-009-9065-y

Keywords

Navigation