Skip to main content

Thinking with External Representations

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

Why do people create extra representations to help them make sense of situations, diagrams, illustrations, instructions and problems? The obvious explanation—external representations save internal memory and computation —is only part of the story. I discuss seven ways external representations enhance cognitive power: they change the cost structure of the inferential landscape ; they provide a structure that can serve as a shareable object of thought ; they create persistent referents; they facilitate re-representation ; they are often a more natural representation of structure than mental representations; they facilitate the computation of more explicit encoding of information ; they enable the construction of arbitrarily complex structure; and they lower the cost of controlling thought—they help coordinate thought. Jointly, these functions allow people to think more powerfully with external representations than without. They allow us to think the previously unthinkable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Although this argument concerns visual processing, it applies equally well to the physical interactions we can perform on the physical object.

  2. 2.

    Reformulation is not limited to formal problem solving. The statement “Police police police police police” is easier to understand when restated at “Police who are policed by police, also police other police”. Most people would not break out their pens to make sense of that statement, but few of us can make sense of it without saying the sentence out loud several times.

  3. 3.

    To see why music can be both referent and representation (terrain and also map) ask whether there is a difference between hearing sound and hearing sound as music. The sound is the terrain; music is the conceptualizing structure that interprets the sound; it maps it.

  4. 4.

    Vygotsky among others has suggested that we mastered thinking externally, by conforming our behavior to social norms of rational inquiry, and that what we learned to do first on the outside we came to do on the inside. Thus, the reason we can do math in our head is because we can do math in the world. The same applies to thinking internally in auditory images. We think in words internally, using auditory images of sounds, because when we think in public we speak. Thinking internally is simulating what we do externally, though Vygotsky did believe that inner speech of adults would be much compressed and unintelligible to anyone except the thinker (Vygotsky 1986).

  5. 5.

    Hutchins (2001).

  6. 6.

    Entry from Wikipedia on Kim Peek the inspiration for the character in the movie Rain Man: “He reads a book in about an hour, and remembers almost everything he has read (…) His reading technique consists of reading the left page with his left eye and the right page with his right eye and in this way can read two pages at time with a rate of about 8–10 s per page. He can recall the content of some 12,000 books from memory. Wikipedia on Kim Peek. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kim_Peek Nov 2009.

  7. 7.

    From Marr (1977, p. 38) “One promising candidate for a Type 2 theory is the problem of predicting how a protein will fold. A large number of influences act on a large polypeptide chain as it flaps and flails in a medium. At each moment only a few of the possible interactions will be important, but the importance of those few is decisive. Attempts to construct a simplified theory must ignore some interactions; but if most interactions are crucial at some stage during the folding, a simplified theory will prove inadequate. Interestingly, the most promising studies of protein folding are currently those that take. a brute force approach, setting up a rather detailed model of the amino acids, the geometry associated with their sequence, hydrophobic interactions with the circumambient fluid, random thermal perturbations etc., and letting the whole set of processes run until a stable configuration is achieved (Levitt and Warshel 1975).”

  8. 8.

    In practice, though not in principle, computers fall into this category. When a workplace has been augmented with tools such as wizards, software agents and the like, it is possible to multiply the potency of basic strategies of interaction to the point where such increases qualitatively change what humans can do, what they can make sense of, and so on. Sometimes our best tools are analog, however, and these are the ones that may provide in principle augmentations to human thought.

References

  • Baddeley, A. D. (2000). The episodic buffer: A new component of working memory? Trends in Cognitive Science, 4, 417–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chabris, C. F., & Hearst, E. S. (2003). Visualization, pattern recognition, and forward search: Effects of playing speed and sight of the position on grandmaster chess errors. Cognitive Science, 27, 637–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, D., & Reisberg, D. (1985). Can mental images be ambiguous? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 11, 317–328.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hegarty, M. (2004). Mechanical reasoning by mental simulation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 280–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (2001). Cognitive artifacts. In R. Wilson & F. Keil (Eds.), The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (2005). Material anchors for conceptual blends. Journal of Pragmatics, 37, 1555–1577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forsythe, W. (2008). http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=0P_4D8c2oGs&feature=related.

  • Kirsh, D. (1992). When is information explicitly represented? The Vancouver Studies in Cognitive Science (pp. 340–365). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D. (1995). The intelligent use of space. Artificial Intelligence, 73, 31–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D. (1996). Adapting the environment instead of oneself. Adaptive Behavior, 4, 415–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D. (2009a). Problem solving and situated cognition. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 264–306). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D. (2009b). Projection, problem space and anchoring. In N. Taatgen, H. van Rijn, J. Nerbonne, & L. Schomaker (Eds.), Proceedings of the 31st Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 2310–2315). Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D. (2009c). Interaction, external representation and sensemaking. In N. Taatgen, H. van Rijn, J. Nerbonne, & L. Schomaker (Eds.), Proceedings of the 31st Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 1103–1108). Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D., & Maglio, P. (1994). On distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic actions. Cognitive Science, 18, 513–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levitt, M., & Warshel, A. (1975). Computer simulation of protein folding. Nature, 253, 694–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Logie, R. H. (1995). Visuo-spatial working memory. Hove, UK: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (1977). Artificial intelligence: A personal view.”. Artificial Intelligence, 9, 37–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E., & Newman, J. (1958). Gödel’s proof. New York: New York University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (2001). Is the imagery debate over? If so, what was it about? In E. Dupoux (Ed.), Language, brain, and cognitive development: Essays in honor of Jacques Mehler (pp. 59–83). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, O. (2008). Musicophilia: Tales of music and the brain. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals: An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann, J. (1948/1961). General and logical theory of automata. In A. H. Taub (Ed.) John von Neumann: Collected works. Volume V: Design of computers, theory of automata and numerical analysis (pp. 288–326). Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. (1986). Thought and language (rev ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Kirsh .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kirsh, D. (2017). Thinking with External Representations. In: Cowley, S., Vallée-Tourangeau, F. (eds) Cognition Beyond the Brain. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49115-8_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49115-8_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-49114-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-49115-8

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics