While we consider that the existing studies on the involvement of IL in our social functioning provide encouraging starting results, we also think that their relevance for the social world is restricted by two main factors: (a) the artificial nature of the surface stimuli (especially in the case of AGL and SRTT) and (b) the static nature of the paradigms themselves, which seldom, if ever, afford the kinds of interactive contexts that nevertheless constitute the core feature of social life.
To overcome these limitations, we developed a novel task consisting of a learning phase and of an awareness test phase. In the learning phase, based on the classic DSC task, participants responded to the cinematic facial expressions of a realistic avatar, with the aim of bringing its facial expression in a predefined state. Unbeknownst to the participants, their responses were related to the avatar’s expressions via a complex equation modeled after Berry and Broadbent (
1984): the equation likewise took into account both the avatar’s previous expression and the participants’ response. Accordingly, the avatar’s expression was influenced by the participants’ response, while the participant had to adapt his/her response to the avatar’s previous expression; in other words, the avatar and the participant were in a continuous interactive loop throughout the learning phase. A significant increase in the number of trials in which the participants managed to bring the avatar in the target state would indicate that they have acquired knowledge from the task. The primary features of the learning phase were that participants were in a continuous interaction with the avatar and the fact that the avatar’s emotional facial expression changed in a cinematic, realistic manner—aspects that give our task an unprecedented level of external validity for studying implicit social learning.
The awareness test phase measured to what extent participants were aware of the information required to regulate the avatar’s state. As the issue of measuring awareness remains highly controversial, we discuss our choices in the following subsection.
The awareness measures
First, we used a subjective measure of awareness. Considering that any awareness measure requires a subjacent theory of consciousness, using a subjective measure is informed by two of the most validated empirical theories of consciousness: the global workspace theory and the higher-order theories. In brief, global workspace theories show that the information one is aware of, is globally available for the cognitive subsystems, including those responsible for verbal reporting of the information. Hence, information one is aware of should be verbally reportable (e.g., Baars,
1997; Dienes,
2012). Higher-order theories are predicated on the principle that one is aware of a mental content only to the extent that one has a meta-representation that one possesses the content (i.e., one knows that one knows something; Rosenthal,
2004). Accordingly, we assessed the existence of such higher-order representations by asking participants to express what they know about their acquired knowledge (Dienes,
2012; Dienes & Scott,
2005; Ling et al.,
2018). An alternative to subjective measures is to use performance-based (so-called “objective”) methods, which equate participants’ above chance performance in tasks that require them to use certain types of knowledge, with them being aware of that knowledge. For instance, in the SRTT, if participants are able to generate a sequence similar to that they have learned, one would conclude that they are aware of the learned sequence. However, it has been found that participants are able to obtain (objectively) above chance performance, even when they (subjectively) report to have no conscious knowledge (e.g., Fu et al.,
2012). Hence, above-chance objective performance can be sustained by subjectively unconscious knowledge (see e.g., Timmermans & Cleeremans,
2015, for a discussion). Of course, introspection is not perfect and subjective methods of measuring awareness have often been criticized (e.g., Berry & Dienes,
1993; Newell & Shanks,
2014: Shanks & St John,
1994; Shanks,
2010). However, most often, the object of criticism has not been their subjective character per se, but rather the manner in which they are typically administered. For example, such measures are often collected after multiple trials/responses from the participant, and hence a failure of introspection can merely reflect forgetting (see the
immediacy criterion of Newell & Shanks,
2014). As a result, most current studies that use subjective measures attempt to ensure conditions that favor an accurate introspection: for example, participants are asked to report on their awareness after each response/trial, they are provided on each trial with written indications of what they have to report, etc. (e.g., Dienes & Scott,
2005; Jurchis et al.,
2020).
Second, a proper measure of awareness needs to precisely specify what content it attempts to capture (see the
relevance criterion of Newell & Shanks,
2014). Dienes and Scott (
2005) have shown that two types of knowledge can operate in implicit learning tasks, namely structural knowledge, and judgement knowledge. Structural knowledge refers to knowledge of the learned regularities. This structural knowledge leads to the development of judgement knowledge, which refers to knowledge of whether a certain response follows or not the regularity. Thus, judgement knowledge is situationally specific and develops on the basis of more general structural knowledge. One cannot have accurate judgement knowledge (cannot know whether an item conforms or not to the learned structure) in the absence of accurate structural knowledge (i.e., without knowing something about the structure) (e.g., Dienes & Scott,
2005; Fu et al.,
2012). Both judgement and structural knowledge can be either conscious or unconscious. Of primary interest for our study, as for the vast majority of implicit learning studies, was whether participants extract
accurate unconscious structural knowledge; that is, accurate knowledge regarding the regularity, the equation, embedded in our learning phase. However, to conclude that the structural knowledge is accurate, one first has to probe that it leads to accurate judgement knowledge, or, more simply put, to accurate judgements/decisions. Hence, the standard, most practical, manner to probe the existence of accurate unconscious or conscious structural knowledge is to have participants make judgements that are based on this knowledge (to accurately determine its accuracy), while asking them to report on their subjective, conscious, access to this knowledge.
To capture the accuracy of participants’ judgement knowledge and the awareness of the underlying structural knowledge, we used two well established measures: the process-dissociation procedure (PDP; Destrebecqz & Cleeremans,
2001; Jacoby,
1991), and a subjective response attribution method (Dienes & Scott,
2005). The process dissociation method measures the accuracy of participants’ judgement knowledge by asking them to either bring or to avoid bringing the avatar in a desired state.
1 The subjective response attribution method asks participants to judge the source of their own responses which, as detailed in the Methods section, reveals the conscious/unconscious status of their structural knowledge. Furthermore, this method also affords an assessment of the conscious/unconscious status of their judgment knowledge (i.e., whether they feel they have some confidence in their response or whether they feel they are just guessing). This method was introduced by Dienes and Scott (
2005) and has become one of the most widely-used subjective methods of assessing awareness across a large variety of IL paradigms, such as the AGL (e.g., Dienes & Scott,
2005; Norman et al.,
2019), the SRTT (Fu et al.,
2012,
2018), evaluative conditioning (Waroquier et al.,
2020), symmetry learning (Ling et al.,
2018), and language learning (Paciorek & Williams,
2015). However, to our knowledge it has never been used in the DSC task.
Some previous DSC studies have found that the judgement knowledge operating in this task is accurate in the sense that, given a situation, participants know what the appropriate response should be. They also found evidence for unconscious structural knowledge in the sense that the accuracy of their judgement knowledge was independent from participants’ objective performance in a recognition task (e.g., Dienes & Fahey,
1998). Accordingly, we expect that our task, which exposes participants to a regularity that is similarly complex and, presumably, difficult to be detected consciously (cf. Jurchis et al.,
2020), will also lead to the development of accurate judgement knowledge sustained by unconscious structural knowledge. We note that previous DSC studies did not assess, in a sensitive manner, the awareness of both structural and judgment knowledge. Berry and Broadbendt (
1984) relied on post-experimental questionnaires that have been criticized by Shanks and St John (
1994) in terms of sensitivity and relevance. Dienes and Fahey (
1998) equated awareness with participants’ objective recognition performance for previous trials, not including other types of knowledge that participants could use (e.g., more abstract rules or heuristics). Saevland and Norman (
2016), in a DSC task, measured participants’ confidence, which indexes only awareness of the judgment knowledge. Hence, for the first time in a DSC task, we aim to sensitively assess the conscious/unconscious status of both structural and judgment knowledge.