Skip to main content
Top
Gepubliceerd in: Psychological Research 2/2012

01-03-2012 | Review

“I” and the brain

Auteur: Beatrice Longuenesse

Gepubliceerd in: Psychological Research | Uitgave 2/2012

Log in om toegang te krijgen
share
DELEN

Deel dit onderdeel of sectie (kopieer de link)

  • Optie A:
    Klik op de rechtermuisknop op de link en selecteer de optie “linkadres kopiëren”
  • Optie B:
    Deel de link per e-mail

Abstract

Many philosophers as well as many biological psychologists think that recent experiments in neuropsychology have definitively discredited any notion of freedom of the will. I argue that the arguments mounted against the concept of freedom of the will in the name of natural causal determinism are valuable but not new, and that they leave intact a concept of freedom of the will that is compatible with causal determinism. After explaining this concept, I argue that it is interestingly related to our use of the first person pronoun “I.” I discuss three examples of our use of “I” in thought and language and submit a few questions I would like neuropsychologists to answer concerning the brain processes that might underlie those uses. I suggest answering these questions would support the compatibilist notion of freedom of the will I have offered in part 1.
Voetnoten
1
See Levine (1983), cited by Chalmers (1996), p.47.
 
2
See e.g. Nagel (1974), Chalmers (1996) and Block (2007).
 
3
See Nagel (1979), Chapter 13: “Panpsychism”.
 
4
As an example, see the discussion in Wegner (2004).
 
5
Baruch Spinoza, Letter to Schuller, October 1674, in Spinoza (1995): 283–286.
 
6
See Libet (1985).
 
7
See Wegner (2002, 2004) and also Rösler (2011), p. 404–406.
 
8
See Frankfurt (1988), Chapters 1–5, esp. Chapter 2. See discussion in Longuenesse and Rösler (2008), esp. p.252.
 
9
According to Frankfurt (1971), both the willing and the unwilling addict are persons, in that for both of them there is an actual issue of endorsing or condemning their first order volition: freely willing what they want is always in question, although only one of them indeed acts of his own free will. In contrast, an individual might be driven by her first order volition to act one way or another without its being a question at all, whether she endorses or rejects her first order willing, i.e. whether her second order volition is in agreement with her first order volition or not. For such an individual Frankfurt coins the term wanton. Many non-human animals as well as very young children are wantons in this sense: they may have freedom of action (they do what they want to do, their first order volition determines them to act or to move one way rather than another) but whether they act of their own free will is not a meaningful question, because whether they want to want what they want, whether they endorse their own want, is not in question. I will say more on this in part 4 of this essay.
 
10
See Wittgenstein (1958), p. 66–74.
 
11
See Perry (1979).
 
12
Of course in (1) the process of reasoning is applied to an abstract proof, whereas in (3) it is applied to a concrete situation. The point here is that as far as the consciousness of myself as implicated in an activity of reasoning, the consciousness is of the same kind. In (3), however, we need in addition a kind of self-consciousness (consciousness of myself as embodied) that is similar to the self-consciousness supporting (2); and a third kind of self-consciousness I will consider below.
 
13
On this point, see Longuenesse (forthcoming).
 
14
Shoemaker (1968).
 
15
de Vignemont (2007) argues that the sense of body-ownership depends not just on one sensory mode (e.g. proprioception or somatosensory information), but on the mutual influence of several different modes, including the influence of vision on tactile experience. Among the experimental studies she cites in support of her thesis is Röder, Rösler and Spence (2004), on the influence of visual information on tactile experience for determining the overall representation of the spatiality of one’s own body.
 
16
See the description of Koffka’s patient Schneider, in Merleau-Ponty (1962), p. 103–112.
 
17
Damasio (1994), p. 223–44, esp. 238–39.
 
18
Kant (1998), A346/B404; B422. Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason is cited in the standard way, by reference to the pagination in the first, 1781 edition (indicated by A) followed by reference to the pagination in the second, B edition (indicated by B).
 
Literatuur
go back to reference Block, N. (2007). Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and brain sciences, 30, 481–548.PubMed Block, N. (2007). Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and brain sciences, 30, 481–548.PubMed
go back to reference Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press. Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.
go back to reference Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error. Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: G.B. Putnam. Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error. Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: G.B. Putnam.
go back to reference Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, lvxiii(1), 5–20 [Repr. as Chapter 2 in Frankfurt (1988)]. Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, lvxiii(1), 5–20 [Repr. as Chapter 2 in Frankfurt (1988)].
go back to reference Frankfurt, H. (1988). The importance of what we care about. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Frankfurt, H. (1988). The importance of what we care about. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
go back to reference Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason, transl. Paul Guyer and Allen Wood, The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. New York: Cambridge University Press. Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason, transl. Paul Guyer and Allen Wood, The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. New York: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361. Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361.
go back to reference Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behavioral and Brain Science, 8, 529–566.CrossRef Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behavioral and Brain Science, 8, 529–566.CrossRef
go back to reference Longuenesse, B. (2011 forthcoming). Two uses of ‘I’ as subject. In S. Posser & F. Récanati (Eds.), Immunity to error through misidentification. Oxford University Press: Oxford. Longuenesse, B. (2011 forthcoming). Two uses of ‘I’ as subject. In S. Posser & F. Récanati (Eds.), Immunity to error through misidentification. Oxford University Press: Oxford.
go back to reference Longuenesse, B., & Rösler, F. (2008). Neurone vergeistigen. Geist und Gehirn im Gespräch. Wissenschaftskolleg zu Berlin, Jahrbuch 2006–2007. Berlin: Heenemann u. Helm. Longuenesse, B., & Rösler, F. (2008). Neurone vergeistigen. Geist und Gehirn im Gespräch. Wissenschaftskolleg zu Berlin, Jahrbuch 2006–2007. Berlin: Heenemann u. Helm.
go back to reference Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of Perception, Transl. Colin Smith, London: Routledge. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of Perception, Transl. Colin Smith, London: Routledge.
go back to reference Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.CrossRef Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.CrossRef
go back to reference Nagel, T. (1979). Mortal questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nagel, T. (1979). Mortal questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
go back to reference Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21 [repr. (with a postscript) in Perry, J. (1993). The problem of the essential indexical and other essays. New York: Oxford University Press: 33–52]. Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21 [repr. (with a postscript) in Perry, J. (1993). The problem of the essential indexical and other essays. New York: Oxford University Press: 33–52].
go back to reference Röder, B., Rösler, F., & Spence, C. (2004). Early vision impairs tactile perception in the blind. Current Biology, 14, 121–124.PubMed Röder, B., Rösler, F., & Spence, C. (2004). Early vision impairs tactile perception in the blind. Current Biology, 14, 121–124.PubMed
go back to reference Rösler, F. (2011). Psychophysiologie der Kognition. Eine Einführung in die kognitive Neurowissenschaft. Heidelberg: Spektrum. Rösler, F. (2011). Psychophysiologie der Kognition. Eine Einführung in die kognitive Neurowissenschaft. Heidelberg: Spektrum.
go back to reference Shoemaker, S. (1968). Self-reference and self-awareness. Journal of Philosophy, 65, 555–567 [repr. in Shoemaker, S. (2003). Identity, cause and mind. New York: Oxford University Press: 6–18]. Shoemaker, S. (1968). Self-reference and self-awareness. Journal of Philosophy, 65, 555–567 [repr. in Shoemaker, S. (2003). Identity, cause and mind. New York: Oxford University Press: 6–18].
go back to reference Spinoza, B. (1995). The Letters, translated by S. Shirley, Introduction and Notes by S. Barbone, L. Rice, and J. Adler, Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett. Spinoza, B. (1995). The Letters, translated by S. Shirley, Introduction and Notes by S. Barbone, L. Rice, and J. Adler, Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett.
go back to reference de Vignemont, F. (2007). Habeas Corpus: the sense of ownership of one’s own body. Mind and Language, 22(4), 427–449. de Vignemont, F. (2007). Habeas Corpus: the sense of ownership of one’s own body. Mind and Language, 22(4), 427–449.
go back to reference Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: MIT Press. Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: MIT Press.
go back to reference Wegner, D. (2004). Précis of the illusion of conscious will. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(5), 649–659 [with discussion: p. 659-79, and Wegner’s response: 679–92]. Wegner, D. (2004). Précis of the illusion of conscious will. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(5), 649–659 [with discussion: p. 659-79, and Wegner’s response: 679–92].
go back to reference Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The blue and brown books. Oxford: Blackwell. Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The blue and brown books. Oxford: Blackwell.
Metagegevens
Titel
“I” and the brain
Auteur
Beatrice Longuenesse
Publicatiedatum
01-03-2012
Uitgeverij
Springer-Verlag
Gepubliceerd in
Psychological Research / Uitgave 2/2012
Print ISSN: 0340-0727
Elektronisch ISSN: 1430-2772
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00426-011-0382-z

Andere artikelen Uitgave 2/2012

Psychological Research 2/2012 Naar de uitgave