Skip to main content

Why Believe in Contentless Beliefs?

  • Chapter
New Essays on Belief

Abstract

This chapter motivates the idea that the most basic kind of believing is a contentless attitude. It gives reasons for thinking that the most basic sort of belief — the sort that both we and other animals adopt toward situations — does not represent those situations in truth-evaluable ways. I call such attitudes pure intentional attitudes. They are not propositional attitudes, which I take to be linguistically mediated intentional attitudes.

Psychology, theory of knowledge and metaphysics revolve about belief, and on the view we take of belief our philosophical outlook largely depends.

— Bertrand Russell, The Analysis of Mind, Lecture xii, 1921

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. 1973, Belief, Truth and Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. 2011, “The Force-Field Puzzle and Mindreading in Non-Human Primates”. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2, 397–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 1998, Language, Thought and Consciousness, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • 2009a, “Mindreading Underlies Metacognition”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32, 121–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • 2009b, “Invertebrate Concepts Confront the Generality Constraint (and Win)”, in Lurz, Ed R. The Philosophy of Animal Minds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 89–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crary, A. 2012, “Dogs and Concepts”, Philosophy, 87 (340), 215–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins R., Blackmon, J., Bird, D., Lee, A. and Roth M. 2006, Representation and Unexploited Content, in Teleosemantics, Macdonald, G. and Papineau, D. (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 195–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 1985, Rational Animals in Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, Lepore, E. and MacLaughlin, B. (eds), Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. 1990a/2008, Information and Representation in Information, Language and Cognition: Vancouver Studies in Cognitive Science, Vol. 1, (Ed P. Hanson), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 175–190 (Reprinted in 2008, Mind and Cognition, (Eds Lycan, W. and Prinz, J.), Oxford: Blackwell, 95–104. Page reference to reprinted version).

    Google Scholar 

  • —. 1990b, A Theory of Content and Other Essays, Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • —. 1991, Fodor’s Guide to Mental Representation in The Future of Folk Psychology, ed. J. Greenwood, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 22–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • —. 2007, The Revenge of the Given in Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind, McLaughlin, B. and Cohen, J. (eds), Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 105–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • —. 2008, “Against Darwinism”, Mind and Language 23, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • —. 2009, “Where Is My Mind?”, London Review of Books, 12 Feb 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauker, C. 2011, Words and Images. An Essay on the Origin of Ideas. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. 2008a, “Alief and Belief”, Journal of Philosophy 105, 634–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • —. 2008b, “Alief in Action (and Reaction)”, Mind and Language 23 (5), 552–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gertler, B. forthcoming, Self-Knowledge and the Transparency of Belief, in Hatzimoysis, A. (ed.), Self-Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2006, Mental Representation, Naturalism and Teleosemantics in Teleosemantics, Macdonald, G. and Papineau, D. (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 42–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunter, D. 2009, Belief, Alienation, and Intention, unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. 1999, The Presence ofMind, Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • —. 2003/2006, Wittgenstein and the End of Philosophy: Neither Theory Nor Therapy, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • —. 2008a, “Limited Engagements and Narrative Extensions”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies 16, 419–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • —. 2008b, Folk Psychological Narratives: The Socio-Cultural Basis of Understanding Reasons, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • —. 2011, “Philosophy of Mind’s New Lease on Life: Autopoietic Enactivism meets Teleosemiotics”, Journal of Consciousness Studies 18(5–6), 44–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • —. 2012, “Exposing The Background: Deep and Local”, in Radman, Z. (ed.), Knowing without Thinking: The Background in Philosophy of Mind, Basingstoke: Palgrave, 37–56

    Google Scholar 

  • —. and Myin, E. 2013, Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds without Content, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., and Pettit, P. 1993, Some Content is Narrow, in Mental Causation, Heil, J. and Mele, A. (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 259–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. 1997, What Minds Can Do, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. 1909, The Meaning of Truth, New York: Longman, Green, and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. 2006, “Teleosemantics and the Consumer”, in Teleosemantics MacDonald, G. and Papineau, D. (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 146–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 1994/1998, “The Content of Perceptual Experience”, The Philosophical Quarterly 44 (175), 190–205. (Reprinted in 1998 in Mind, Value and Reality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 341–358. Page references to reprinted version).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. 1984, Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • —. 1993, White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • —. 2004, Varieties of Meaning: The 2002 Jean Nicod Lectures, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • —. 2005, Language: A Biological Model, Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1992, Renewing Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. M. 2007, Representation Reconsidered, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. 2007, Rethinking Commonsense Psychology: A Critique of Folk Psychology, Theory of Mind and Simulation, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. 2008. “Farewell to Folk Psychology: A Response to Hutto”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies 16(3), 445–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowbottom, D. 2007, “In-Between Believing and Degrees of Belief”, Teorema 26, 131–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. 2006, Body Language, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. 2010, “Acting Contrary to our Professed Beliefs or the Gulf between Occurent Judgement and Dispositional Belief”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91, 531–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W. 2000, Theories of Consciousness, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J. 1983, Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. 2011, Embodied Cognition, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommers, F. 2009, “Dissonant Beliefs”, Analysis 69, 267–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. 1998, “What Might Nonconceptual Content be?”, Philosophical Issues 9, 339–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. 1979, “Do Animals Have Beliefs?”, The Australasian Journal of Philosophy 57, 15–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. 2005. Reconstructing the Cognitive World, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams. B. 1973. Problems of the Self, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. 2007, The Philosophy of Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, A. 2007, “The Nature of Belief”, Journal of Consciousness Studies 14, 11, 61–82.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2013 Daniel D. Hutto

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hutto, D.D. (2013). Why Believe in Contentless Beliefs?. In: Nottelmann, N. (eds) New Essays on Belief. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137026521_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics