Skip to main content

The Causal Implications of Mechanistic Thinking: Identification Using Directed Acyclic Graphs (DAGs)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Causal Analysis for Social Research

Part of the book series: Handbooks of Sociology and Social Research ((HSSR))

Abstract

In analyzing causal claims, the most common evidentiary strategy is to use an experimental or quasi-experimental framework; holding all else constant, a treatment is varied and its effect on the outcome is determined. However, a second, quite distinct strategy is gaining prominence within the social sciences. Rather than mimic an experiment, researchers can identify causal relations by finding evidence for mechanisms that link cause and effect. In this chapter, we use Directed Acyclic Graphs (DAGs) to illustrate the power of using mechanisms. We show how mechanisms can aid in causal analysis by bringing additional variation to bear in instances where causal effects would otherwise not be identified. Specifically, we examine five generic situations where a focus on mechanisms using DAGs allows an analyst to warrant causal claims.

Authors listed in alphabetical order.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As shown by Pearl (2000, 2009), this approach is fully derivable from structural equation models.

  2. 2.

    As frequently pointed out by Pearl, the potential outcome framework is fully consistent with and can be derived from structural equation theory (Pearl 2009, p. 228; Chap. 15 by Bollen and Pearl, this volume).

  3. 3.

    In situations where the effect of T and M interact in affecting Y and T affects Y independently of M, there are multiple possible definitions of what constitutes T’s direct and indirect effect since they will depend on the level of Y. We do not discuss this issue here further. Robins and Greenland (1992) provide an overview.

  4. 4.

    Some philosophers of science, for example, believe the counterfactual criterion to be neither sufficient nor necessary for causation. We do not review these limitations here.

  5. 5.

    Our notion of modularity is closely related to Pearl’s (2000, 2009) idea of surgically intervening in a causal process by changing the value of one variable holding others constant, what he calls his “Do” operator.

  6. 6.

    The literature on complex systems would describe a situation where (Fig. 14.1a) and (Fig. 14.1c) held as one of “supervenience”—that is, a case where a particular higher-order phenomena, here A → B, is the result of any one of two or more different separate lower-level processes, here A → M 1 → B or A → M 2 → B, and that there can be no change in the higher-order process without a change in the lower-order processes (Sawyer 2005).

  7. 7.

    Elwert and Winship (2012) provide a lengthy discussion of these phenomena showing that a wide range of methodological biases are due to it. Furthermore, they describe a host of social science examples where this bias is present.

  8. 8.

    Elwert and Winship (2012) show that in general the direction of the association may be either positive or negative when a collider has been conditioned on.

  9. 9.

    For a formal definition of identifiability, see Pearl (2009, p. 77).

  10. 10.

    A “descendant” of a variable is a variable that is either directly or indirectly caused by a variable.

  11. 11.

    In a seminal paper, Angrist et al. (1996) show that when the effect of T on Y is heterogeneous, the traditional IV estimator only estimates the average causal effect of T on Y for those individuals whose behavior is shifted by Z, giving what they term the “local average treatment effect.” Of course in this situation, we would need to add to the DAG in Fig. 14.5 a variable W * that captured this heterogeneity and it is affecting both T and Y. If Z and W * were associated, then traditional IV identification would no longer hold as there would be an unblocked path going from Z to W * to Y. See section 7.5.1 of Morgan and Winship (2010) for further explanation.

  12. 12.

    Criteria (1) and (2) need also to prohibit the possibility that by conditioning on a variable in order to block a path, one has not conditioned on a collider and thus induced a new unblocked path. See Elwert and Winship (2012) for a discussion of situations where if one is considering conditioning on a variable, one is “damned if you do and damned if you don’t.”

  13. 13.

    As noted above, a causal DAG includes all common determinants of variables in the DAG.

  14. 14.

    If Wages = f(Effort, Bias *) and Effort = g(Kids), then the convolution is found by substitution giving Wages = f(g(Kids), Bias *).

  15. 15.

    Note that causal graphs of this kind fall into what Pearl (2012) and Avin et al. (2005) term “broken-fork models.” As such, we cannot identify the path-specific effect from Kids → Bias → Effort → Wages, even if we could observe all of these variables.

  16. 16.

    Arguably, there should also be a direct arrow in this diagram going from Kids to Effort, representing the fact that even with childcare, the presence of children might reduce a woman’s work effort. In order to keep things simple, however, we will assume here that childcare eliminates any tendency for woman with kids to work less. This might be a reasonable assumption if the organization itself provided childcare.

References

  • Anderson, D. J., Binder, M., & Krause, K. (2003). Motherhood wage penalty revisited: Experience, heterogeneity, work effort, and work-schedule flexibility. Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 56(2), 273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angrist, J. D., Imbens, G. W., & Rubin, D. B. (1996). Identification of causal effects using instrumental variables. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 91, 445–455.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avin, C., Shpitser, I., & Pearl, J. (2005). Identifiability of path-specific effects. In Proceedings of International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 357–363). Edinburgh, Scotland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2006). Discovering cell mechanisms. The creation of modern cell biology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanism. Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. S. (1985). Human capital, effort, and the sexual division of labor. Journal of Labor Economics, 3(1), 33–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, A. (2008). Process tracing: A Bayesian perspective. In J. Box-Steffensmeier, H. E. Brady, & D. Collier (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of political methodology (pp. 217–270). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bollen, K. (2012). Instrumental variables in sociology and the social sciences. Annual Review of Sociology, 38, 37–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Budig, M. J., & England, P. (2001). The wage penalty for motherhood. American Sociological Review, 66, 204–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1997). Mechanism and explanation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 27, 410–465.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2004). How does it work? The search for explanatory mechanisms. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34, 182–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, D., Brady, H. E., & Seawright, J. (2010). Sources of leverage in causal inference: Toward an alternative view of methodology. In H. E. Brady & D. Collier (Eds.), Rethinking social inquiry: Diverse tools, shared standards (2nd ed., pp. 161–199). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correll, S. J., Benard, S., & Paik, I. (2007). Getting a job: Is there a motherhood penalty? American Journal of Sociology, 112(5), 1297–1339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain. Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2002). Strategies for discovering mechanisms: Schema instantiation, modular subassembly, forward/backward chaining. Philosophy of Science, 69(S3), 354–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries. Essays on mechanisms, interfield relations, and anomaly resolution. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, O. D., Featherman, D. L., & Duncan, B. (1972). Socioeconomic background and achievement. New York: Seminar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1989). Nuts and bolts for the social sciences. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1999). Alchemies of the mind: Rationality and the emotions. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (2007). Explaining social behavior: More nuts and bolts for the social sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elwert, F., & Winship, C. (2012). Endogenous selection. Unpublished paper, University of Wisconsin.

    Google Scholar 

  • George, A. L., & Bennett, A. (2005). Case studies and theory development in the social sciences. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerring, J. (2007). Review article: The mechanistic worldview. Thinking inside the box. British Journal of Political Science, 38, 161–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerring, J. (2010). Causal mechanisms: Yes, but…. Comparative Political Studies, 43(11), 1499–1526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342–S353.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, N. (2009). A pragmatist theory of social mechanisms. American Sociological Review, 74(3), 358–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, P. (2005). Dissecting the social. On the principles of analytical sociology. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedstrom, P., & Bearman, P. (2009). The Oxford handbook of analytic sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedstrom, P., & Swedberg, R. (1996). Social mechanisms. Acta Sociologica, 39(3), 281–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedstrom, P., & Ylikoski, P. (2010). Causal mechanisms in the social sciences. Annual Review of Sociology, 36, 49–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739). A treatise on human nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Imai, K., Keele, L., Tingley, D., & Yamamoto, T. (2011). Unpacking the black box of causality: Learning about causal mechanisms from experimental and observational studies. American Political Science Review, 105(4), 265–289.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendall, P. L., & Lazarsfeld, P. (1950). Problems of survey analysis. In R. K. Merton & P. F. Lazarsfeld (Eds.), Continuities in social research: Studies in the scope and methods of “The American Soldier” (pp. 133–196). Glencoe: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, G., Keohane, R. O., & Verba, S. (1994). Designing social inquiry: Scientific inference in qualitative research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (1986). The scientific Marx. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, D. (1991). Varieties of social explanation: An introduction to the philosophy of social science. Boulder: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahoney, J. (2012). The logic of process tracing tests in the social sciences. Sociological Methods & Research, 41(4), 570–597.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, S. L., & Winship, C. (2007). Counterfactuals and causal inference: Methods and principles for social research. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, S. L., & Winship, C. (2010). Bringing context and variability back in to causal analysis. In H. Kincaid (Ed.), Oxford handbook of the philosophy of the social sciences (pp. 319–354). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning and inference. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2010). On measurement bias in causal inference. In P. Grunwald, & P. Spirtes (Eds.), Proceedings of UAI (pp. 425–432). Corvallis: AUAI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2012). The causal mediation formula—A guide to the assessment of pathways and mechanisms. Prevention Science, 13(4), 426–436.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reskin, B. (2003). Including mechanisms in our models of ascriptive inequality. American Sociological Review, 68, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robins, J., & Greenland, S. (1992). Identifiability and exchangeability for direct and indirect effects. Epidemiology, 3(2), 143–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer, R. K. (2005). Social emergence: Societies as complex systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, M. E. (2008). Identification of causal parameters in randomized studies with mediating variables. Journal of Educational and Behavioral Statistics, 33(2), 230–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swedberg, R. (2000). Max Weber and the idea of economic sociology. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • VanderWeele, T. (2009). Mediation and mechanism. European Journal of Epidemiology, 24, 217–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • VanderWeele, T. J., & Robins, J. M. (2007). Directed acyclic graphs, sufficient causes, and the properties of conditioning on a common effect. American Journal of Epidemiology, 166(9), 1096–1104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winship, C., & Harding, D. (2008). A mechanism-based approach to the identification of age-period-cohort models. Sociological Methods & Research, 36(3), 363–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2002). What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science, 69(3S), 366–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2005). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P. (2011). Social mechanisms and explanatory relevance. In P. Demeulenaere (Ed.), Analytical sociology and social mechanisms. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors wish to thank Steve Morgan, Judea Pearl, Tyler VanderWeele, Chris Muller, and Joe Krupnick for helpful comments. Of course, any remaining errors are the authors’ responsibility.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carly R. Knight .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Knight, C.R., Winship, C. (2013). The Causal Implications of Mechanistic Thinking: Identification Using Directed Acyclic Graphs (DAGs). In: Morgan, S. (eds) Handbook of Causal Analysis for Social Research. Handbooks of Sociology and Social Research. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6094-3_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics