Skip to main content

Reconsidering the Metaphysics of Science from the Inside Out

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Neuroscience, Consciousness and Spirituality

Abstract

Material reductionism – the prevailing metaphysical view that reality can be understood entirely in terms of non-conscious physical stuff – is at odds with the existence of experience, the flow of time, and the privileged present. We propose an alternative scientifically-grounded metaphysical perspective that posits: (1) Consciousness represents a fundamental aspect of reality such that all material things enjoy some varying degree of consciousness (panpsychism); (2) nervous systems entail a nested hierarchy of distinct conscious observers; (3) both experience and the flow of time suggest the reality of a subjective realm of existence; (4) the flow of time suggests a process by which all observers collectively sample segments of continuous space/time at different rates, creating a composite of experienced moments of varying thickness; (5) the possibility that consciousness can influence the duration and selection of experienced moments affords a possible opportunity for genuine free will. Although speculative, these conjectures illustrate the type of alternative metaphysics that may be able to accommodate scientific observations without abandoning the self-evident facts that experience exists and time flows.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    How phenomenal experience fits into this model has been a source of some consternation. In some places Dennett seems to suggest that phenomenal experience is just an illusion (Dennett 1991) and indeed many have interpreted him in this way (e.g. Searle 1990). In other places, however, he insists that we are conscious (Dennet 1997). Given that Dennett consistently denies that subjective experience offers any privileged information a critical question arises for him, namely, how it is that he knows that he is conscious.

  2. 2.

    Hunt parts ways with the Schoolers on the ideas in this section due to its postulation of an ontological distinction between information and physical/reality, see Afterword.

  3. 3.

    Hunt parts ways with the Schoolers on this section due to its endorsement of a block universe model of physical reality, and its suggestion of an ontological distinction between subjective and objective time (see Afterword).

  4. 4.

    In this regard is notable that information theory specifically requires that observations proceed in discrete steps rather than being continuous. As Turing observes “It is easy to show using standard theory that if a system starts in an eigenstate of some observable, and measurements are made of that observable N times a second, then, even if the state is not a stationary one, the probability that the system will be in the same state after, say, one second, tends to one as N tends to infinity; that is, that continual observations will prevent motion …” Alan Turing quoted in Teuscher 2003 (p. 54)

  5. 5.

    We note that this account shares some at least superficial similarity with the physicist Lynd’s (2003) discussions of the relationship between subjective and physical instantiations of time. Lynd observes “there is not a precise static instant in time underlying a dynamical physical process… it is the human observer who subjectively projects, imposes and assigns a precise instant in time upon a physical process, for example, in order to gain a meaningful subjective picture or “mental snapshot” of the relative position of a body in relative motion” (p. 2).

  6. 6.

    We thank Rachel Schooler for this observation.

  7. 7.

    Striking evidence from binocular rivalry studies (in which competing images are presented to each eye) suggest that while the magnitude of such synchronizations is greatest for the reported percept, synchronization is also associated with the image that is not currently being reported (Srinivasan et al. 2009). This suggests that in binocular rivalry experiments, a conscious experience of both images is maintained in the visual system and reflected by distinct coherent patterns of oscillation associated with each. However, at any one time only one of those conscious experiences is integrated into the higher order experience associated with the observer that is capable of verbal report.

References

  • Abbott, E. A. (1885). Flatland: A romance of many dimensions. Boston: Roberts Bothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aspect, A., et al. (1982). Experimental realization of Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen-Bohm Gedanken experiment: A new violation of Bell’s inequalities. Physical Review Letters, 49, 91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bars, I., Deliduman, C., & Andreev, O. (1998). Gauged duality, conformal symmetry, and spacetime with two times. Physical Review, D58, 066004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R. F. (2008a). Free will, consciousness, and cultural animals. In J. Baer, J. C. Kaufman, & R. F. Baumeister (Eds.), Are we free? Psychology and free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R. F. (2008b). Social reality and the hole in determinism. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 18(1), 34–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & Vohs, K. D. (2011). Do conscious thoughts cause behavior? Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 331–361.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1912). Matter and memory. New York: McMillan (Original Work Published 1896).

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1734/1971). A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge. Menston: Scolar Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. (2004). Descartes’ baby: How the science of child development explains what makes us human. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1974). “Downward causation” in hierarchically organized biological systems. In F. J. Ayala & T. Dobzhansky (Eds.), Studies in the philosophy of biology (pp. 179–186). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1995a). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1995b). The puzzle of conscious experience. Scientific American, 273(6), 91–100.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. (1994). The astonishing hypothesis: The scientific search for the soul. New York: Scribner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. (2002). That mysterious flow. Scientific American, 287(3), 40–43.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (2006). The god delusion. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Broglie, L. (1959). A general survey of the scientific work of Albert Einstein. In P. A. Shilpp (Ed.), Albert Einstein: Philosopher-scientist. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennet, D. C. (1997). Kinds of minds: Towards an understanding of consciousness. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2003). Freedom evolves. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1956). Discourse on method. New York: Liberal Arts Press (Original Work Published 1637).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyson, F. J. (1979). Disturbing the universe. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (2001). Relativity: The special and the general theory (Reprint of 1920 Robert W. Lawson Ed. & trans.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. (1999). The pleasure of finding things out: The best short works of Richard P. Feynman. Cambridge: Perseus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, W. T. (2008). Nano-intentionality: A defense of intrinsic intentionality. Biology and Philosophy, 23(2), 157–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, W. J., & Vitiello, G. (2006). Nonlinear brain dynamics as macroscopic manifestation of underlying many-body field dynamics. Physics of Life Reviews, 3(2), 93–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. S. (2005). Forty-five years of split-brain research and still going strong. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 6(8), 653–659.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, B. (2004). The fabric of the cosmos: Space, time, and the texture of reality. New York: A.A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, D. R. (2007). Whitehead’s radically different postmodern philosophy: An argument for its contemporary relevance. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hameroff, S. (2001). Time, consciousness and quantum events in fundamental space-time geometry. In R. Buccheri, M. Saniga, & W. Stuckey (Eds.), The nature of time: Geometry, physics and perception. Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hameroff, S. (2010). The “conscious pilot”-dendritic synchrony moves through the brain to mediate consciousness. Journal of Biological Physics, 36(1), 71–93.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hameroff, S. R., & Penrose, R. (1996). Conscious Events as Orchestrated Space-Time Selections, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(1), pp. 36–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, S. (2006). Then a miracle occurs [Cartoon]. New Yorker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hiley, B. J., & Peat, F. D. (1987). Quantum implications: Essays in honour of David Bohm. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann, B., & Dukas, H. (1972). Albert Einstein, creator and rebel. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D. R. (2007). I am a strange loop. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, T. (2010). Mind, world, god. Unpublished manuscript, UC Santa Barbara, Santa Barbara.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, T. (in press). Kicking the psychophysical laws into gear: A new approach to the combination problem, part 1. Journal of Consciousness Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1980). Phenomenology and the foundations of the sciences. The Hague: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1898). Human immortality: Two supposed objections to the doctrine. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin and Co.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1909). A pluralistic universe. New York: Longmans, Green, and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1917). “Human Immortality” Ingersoll lectures, 1897–1898. London: J. M.Dent & Sons, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1918). The principles of psychology. New York: Henry Holt and Company. (Original work published 1890)

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (2002). Varieties of religious experience: A study in human nature. New York: Random House (Original Work Published 1902).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jammer, M. (2006). Concepts of simultaneity: From antiquity to Einstein and beyond. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kam, J. W. Y., Dao, E., Farley, J., Fitzpatrick, K., Smallwood, J., Schooler, J. W., & Handy, T. C. (2011). Slow fluctuations in attentional control of sensory cortex. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23(2), 460–470.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1781/1896). Critique of pure reason (F. M. Muller Trans.). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingstone, A., Tipper, C. M., Ristic, J., & Ngan, E. T. C. (2004). The Eyes Have It!: An fMRI Investigation. Brain and Cognition, 55(2), 269–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koch, C. (2004). The quest for consciousness: A neurobiological approach. Englewood: Roberts and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koestler, A. (1978). Janus: A summing up. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1996). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press (Original Work Published 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. (1989). Monadology. In R. Ariew & D. Garber (Eds. & Trans.), G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical essays. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. (Original work published 1714)

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (2004). Mind time: The temporal factor in consciousness, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Linde, A. D. (1990). Particle physics and inflationary cosmology. Chur: Harwood Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linde, A. D. (2004). Inflation, quantum cosmology, and the anthropic principle. In J. D. Barrow, P. C. W. Davies, & C. L. Harper (Eds.), Science and ultimate reality: Quantum theory, cosmology, and complexity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E. F., & Schooler, J. W. (1985). Information processing conceptualizations of human cognition: Past, present and future. In B. D. Ruben (Ed.), Information & behavior (pp. 225–251). New Brunswick: Transaction Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorentz, H. A. (1895). Versuch einer Theorie der electrischen und optischen Erscheinungen in bewegten Körpern. Leiden: E.J Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorentz, H. A. (1899). Simplified theory of electrical and optical phenomena in moving systems. Proceedings of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences, 1, 427–442.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynds, P. (2003). Time and classical and quantum mechanics: Indeterminacy versus discontinuity. Foundations of Physics Letters, 16(4), 343–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margulis, L., & Sagan, D. (1995). What is life? New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1991). The problem of consciousness: Essays towards a resolution. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1999). Consciousness and space. In J. Shear (Ed.), Explaining consciousness: The hard problem. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McTaggart, J. E. (1908). The unreality of time. Mind, 17(64), 457–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Minsky, M. L. (1986). The society of mind. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1989). The emperor’s new mind: Concerning computers, minds, and the laws of physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. New York: Norton & Company, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2007). The blank slate. New York: Viking Adult.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (trans. 2008). The republic (B. Jowett, Trans.). New York: Cosimo Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proulx, T., & Heine, S. J. (2006). Death and black diamonds: Meaning, mortality, and the meaning maintenance model. Psychological Inquiry, 17(4), 309–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, G. (2005). A place for consciousness: Probing the deep structure of the natural world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salart, D., et al. (2008). Spacelike separation in a Bell test assuming gravitationally induced collapses. Physical Review Letters, 100(22), 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schooler, J. W. (2002). Re-representing consciousness: Dissociations between experience and meta-consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(8), 339–344.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Schooler, J. N. (2010). Mental inertia: Limited free will and determinism. Paper submitted in fulfillment of UCSB Research Mentorship program, University of California, Santa Barbara.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schooler, J. N. (2011) Mental laws: The relationship of mentality and physics. Unpublished manuscript, San Marcos High School, San Marcos

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1995). The world as will and idea: Abridged in one volume. London: J.M. Dent (Original Work Published 1819).

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1990). Is the brain’s mind a computer program? Scientific American, 262(1), 26–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shariff, A., Schooler, J. W., & Vohs, K. (2009). The hazards of claiming to have solved the hard problem of free will. In J. Baer & R. Baumeister (Eds.), Psychology and free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skrbina, D. (2005). Panpsychism in the West. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smythies, J. (2003). Space, time and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(3), 47–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1985). Ethics. In E. Curley (Ed. & Trans.), The collected works of Spinoza (Vol. I). Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1677)

    Google Scholar 

  • Srinivasan, R., Russell, D. P., Edelman, G. M., & Tononi, G. (2009). Increased synchronization of neuromagnetic responses during conscious perception. Journal of Neuroscience, 19(13), 5435–5448.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1974). Freedom and resentment, and other essays. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2008). Real materialism and other essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talbot, M. (1991). The holographic universe. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teuscher, C. (2003). Alan turing: Life and legacy of a great thinker. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G. (2008). Consciousness as integrated information: A provisional manifesto. The Biological Bulletin, 215(3), 216–242.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, B. A. (2010, February 25–27) Toward a three-dimensional science of the mind. Paper presented at Neuroscience, Consciousness and Spirituality Meeting 2010: Meditation and Prayer: Neuroscientific Approaches and Philosophical Implications, Freiburg. Available at http://www.uniklinik-freiburg.de/medmed/live/events/Expert-Meeting-Neuroscience-Consciousness-and-Spirituality-2010/Wallace_Three-Dimensional.pdf.

  • Watts, A. (1991). Man, nature, and the nature of man, collected public lectures. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiskrantz, L., & Weiskrantz, L. (2009). Blindsight: A case study spanning 35 years and new developments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1929). Process and reality: An essay in cosmology. Cambridge: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeki, S. (2003). The disunity of consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(5), 214–218.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Zeki, S., & Bartels, A. (1999). Toward a theory of visual consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 8(2), 225–259.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to many individuals for their input and assistance with this chapter. Ben Baird provided comments on numerous drafts and assisted with references. The ideas presented here were helpfully refined by discussions with many people, none of whom should be assumed to endorse the resulting product. These include: Daniel Povinelli, Merrill McSpadden, Carmi Schooler, Lael Schooler, Rachel Schooler, Nina Schooler, Roy Baumeister, Daniel Gilbert, Daniel Dennett, Mark Laufer, Jonathan Smallwood, Christine Tipper, Dianne Tice, Thomas Nadelhofer, and Harvey Bottelsen. The writing of this chapter was supported by grants from the James Bower Foundation and the Bial Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan W. Schooler .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schooler, J.W., Hunt, T., Schooler, J.N. (2011). Reconsidering the Metaphysics of Science from the Inside Out. In: Walach, H., Schmidt, S., Jonas, W. (eds) Neuroscience, Consciousness and Spirituality. Studies in Neuroscience, Consciousness and Spirituality, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2079-4_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics