Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Studies in Brain and Mind ((SIBM,volume 9))

Abstract

Regarding the present experience in the here and now, the question arises as to what the temporal limits of conscious awareness are. At least three levels of temporal present pertaining to temporal integration with different duration can be discerned: (1) in the range of milliseconds, the functional moment defines whether events are perceived as simultaneous or as appearing temporally ordered; (2) in the range of up to 2 or 3 s, the experienced moment is related to temporal segmentation which enables the conscious awareness of the present moment; (3) in the range of multiple seconds, continuity of experience is formed by working memory processes leading to the sense of mental presence. Present experience is a single unitary state. Therefore, experiences on lower levels of temporal integration are embedded and discontinuously fused into the highest level of integration: mental presence. Events occurring within an experienced moment are phenomenally present and integrated into working memory-related mental presence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See the distinction between absolute and relative presence by Sean Enda Power’s Chap. 5 of this volume. My analysis is consistent with the concept of relative presence which can be durational. Absolute presence would be punctual.

  2. 2.

    Dan Lloyd (2004, 2012) provides an intuitive example for a temporal field in music. Someone familiar with the Beatles song “Hey Jude,” when she hears Paul McCartney start to sing the “Hey” accompanied with the well-known tune will automatically anticipate the “Jude.” The “Jude” is somehow present but it actually physically not yet existent (the recording could suddenly be interrupted). When McCartney sings the “Jude” the “Hey” is still somehow present although no longer physically there. “Hey Jude” forms a unit of present experience.

  3. 3.

    Just as an aside: Why would the neural system create a mechanism which lets the eye blinks get unnoticed? Indeed the duration of 200–250 ms is quite long. But functionally, a top-down mechanism does not compensate for the loss of visual input. Is this mechanism for letting eye blinks go unnoticed an indication that phenomenal consciousness beyond functionality is an important feature for the conscious observer?

  4. 4.

    This statement may only relate to the conscious awareness of temporal ordering. In certain visual temporal integration tasks it has been shown that some temporal-order processing may still happen on an unconscious level (Giersch et al. 2013; Pilz et al. 2013). Importantly, this unconscious coding of temporal ordering has been discussed creating a feeling for the continuous passage of time.

  5. 5.

    The phenomenal experience related to listening to the sequence of these stimuli is not easy to capture. Although with a stimulus-onset asynchrony of 300 ms one has the clear impression of four consecutive sounds, one has yet to “replay” them several times in one’s mind to come up with a definite answer. One could argue that temporal order is only inferred from a retrospective perspective after the perceptual gestalt has been perceived. The ordering of four cards representing the four different sounds makes the task definitely easier. I can provide probe stimuli in wav format with various stimulus-onset asynchronies for a personal listening experience.

References

  • Atmanspacher, Harald, Thomas Filk, and Hartmann Römer. 2004. Quantum zeno features of bistable perception. Biological Cybernetics 90: 33–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benovsky, Jiri. 2013. The present vs. the specious present. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 4: 193–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, Vittorio. 1913. Psychologie der Zeitauffassung. Heidelberg: Carl Winters Universitätsbuchhandlung.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bristow, Davina, John-Dylan Haynes, Richard Sylvester, Christopher Frith, and Geraint Rees. 2005. Blinking suppresses the neural response to unchanging retinal stimulation. Current Biology 15: 1296–1300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Busch, Niko, and Rufin VanRullen. 2014. Is visual perception like a continuous flow or a series of snapshots? In Subjective time: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of temporality, ed. Valtteri Arstila and Dan Lloyd, 161–178. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caffier, Philipp, Udo Erdmann, and Peter Ullsperger. 2003. Experimental evaluation of eye-blink parameters as a drowsiness measure. European Journal of Applied Physiology 89: 319–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, (A.D.). Bud. 2009. How do you feel—now? The anterior insula and human awareness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 10: 59–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, Barry. 2000. Stream of consciousness. Abindgon: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, Barry. 2008. Sensing change. Philosophical Issues 18: 362–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, Barry. 2010. Temporal consciousness. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-temporal/. Accessed 17 May 2014.

  • Exner, Sigmund. 1875. Experimentelle Untersuchung der einfachsten psychischen Processe. III. Abhandlung. Pflügers Archiv für die Gesamte Physiologie 11: 403–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fink, Martina, Pamela Ulbrich, Jan Churan, and Marc Wittmann. 2006. Stimulus-dependent processing of temporal order. Behavioral Processes 71: 344–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fraisse, Paul. 1984. Perception and estimation of time. Annual Review in Psychology 35: 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franck, Georg. 2012. What kind of being is mental presence? Toward a novel analysis of the hard problem of consciousness. Mind and Matter 10: 9–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fujisaki, Waka, and Shin’ya Nishida. 2010. A common perceptual temporal limit of binding synchronous inputs across different sensory attributes and modalities. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 277: 2281–2290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Shaun. 2000. Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4: 14–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Shaun. 2013. A pattern theory of self. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7(443).

    Google Scholar 

  • Giersch, Anne, Laurence Lalanne, Mitsouko van Assche, and Mark A. Elliott. 2013. On disturbed time continuity in schizophrenia: an elementary impairment in visual perception? Frontiers in Psychology 4(281).

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman-Rakic, Patricia. 1997. Space and time in the mental universe. Nature 386: 559–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirsh, Ira J., and Carl E. Sherrick Jr. 1961. Perceived order in different sense modalities. Journal of Experimental Psychology 62: 423–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoerl, Christoph. 2009. Time and tense in perceptual experience. Philosopher’s Imprint 9: 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoerl, Christoph. 2013. A succession of feelings, in and of itself, is not a feeling of succession. Mind 122: 373–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holcombe, Alex O. 2009. Seeing slow and seeing fast: Two limits on perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13: 216–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1928. Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewußtseins. Halle: Max Niemeyer Verlag. English edition: Husserl, Edmund. 1991. Lectures on the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time. In On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time (1893–1917). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, William. 1890. The principles of psychology. London: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, Julian. 2009. The minimal sense of self, temporality and the brain. Psyche 15: 59–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, Julian. 2010. Making sense of phenomenal unity: An intentionalist account of temporal experience. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 85: 155–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, Julian, and Valtteri Arstila. 2013. Time in mind. In A companion to the philosophy of time, ed. Heather Dyke and Adrian Bardon, 444–469. Chichester: Wiley.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, Dan. 2004. Radiant cool: A novel theory of consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, Dan. 2012. Neural correlates of temporality: Default mode variability and temporal awareness. Consciousness and Cognition 21: 695–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • London, Justin. 2002. Cognitive constraints on metric systems: Some observations and hypotheses. Music Perception 19: 529–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martinez-Conde, Susana, Stephen Macknik, Xoana Troncoso, and David Hubel. 2009. Microsaccades: A neurophysiological analysis. Trends in Neurosciences 32: 463–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mates, Jiří, Ulrike Müller, Tomáš Radil, and Ernst Pöppel. 1994. Temporal in sensorimotor synchronization. Journal Cognitive Neuroscience 6: 332–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAuley, J. Devin, Mari Riess Jones, Shayla Holub, Heather M. Johnston, and Nathaniel S. Miller. 2006. The time of our lives: Life span development of timing and event tracking. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 135: 348–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, Thomas. 2004. Being no one: The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miyazaki, Makoto, Shinya Yamamoto, Sunao Uchida, and Shigeru Kitazawa. 2006. Bayesian calibration of simultaneity in tactile temporal order judgment. Nature Neuroscience 9: 875–877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mölder, Bruno. 2014. How philosophical models explain time consciousness. Procedia—Social and Behavioral Sciences 126: 48–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montemayor, Carlos. 2013. Minding time: A theoretical and philosophical approach to the psychology of time. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Thomas. 1974. What it is like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review 83: 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nakajima, Yoshitaka, Shinsuku Shimojo, and Yoichi Sugita. 1980. On the perception of two successive sound bursts. Psychological Research 41: 335–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Michael. 1989. The relationship between variability of intertap intervals and interval duration. Psychological Research 51: 38–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, Lloyd R., and Margaret J. Peterson. 1959. Short-term retention of individual verbal items. Journal of Experimental Psychology 58: 193–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pilz, Karin S., Christina Zimmermann, Janine Scholz, and Michael H. Herzog. 2013. Long-lasting visual integration of form, motion, and color as revealed by visual masking. Journal of Vision 13: 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poggel, Dorothe, Bernhard Treutwein, Claudia Calmanti, and Hans Strasburger. 2012. The Tölz temporal topography study: Mapping the visual field across the life span. Part I: The topography of light detection and temporal-information processing. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics 74: 1114–1132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pöppel, Ernst. 1988. Mindworks: Time and conscious experience. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pöppel, Ernst. 2009. Pre-semantically defined window for cognitive processing. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364: 1887–1896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pöppel, Ernst, Kerstin Schill, and Nicole von Steinbüchel. 1990. Sensory integration within temporally neutral system states: A hypothesis. Naturwissenschaften 77: 89–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Power, Sean. 2012. The metaphysics of the “specious” present. Erkenntnis 77: 121–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rammsayer, Thomas, and Eckart Altenmüller. 2006. Temporal information processing in musicians and nonmusicians. Music Perception 24: 37–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rashbrook, Oliver. 2013. The continuity of consciousness. European Journal of Philosophy 21: 611–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo, Antti. 2006. Inner presence: Consciousness as a biological phenomenon. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, John, M. Concetta Morrone, Michael E. Goldberg, and David C. Burr. 2001. Changes in visual perception at the time of saccades. Trends in Neuroscience 24: 113–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, David C., and Amy E. Wenzel. 1996. One hundred years of forgetting: A quantitative description of retention. Psychological Review 103: 734–760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seth, Anil K., Keisuke Suzuki, and Hugo D. Critchley. 2012. An interoceptive predictive coding model of conscious presence. Frontiers in Psychology 2: 395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, William. 1897. Psychische Präsenzzeit. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und die Physiologie der Sinnesorgane 13: 325–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szelag, Elzbieta, Nicole von Steinbüchel, Mathias Reiser, Ernst Gilles de Langen, and Ernst Pöppel. 1996. Temporal constraints in processing of nonverbal rhythmic patterns. Acta Neurobiologiae Experimentalis 56: 215–225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, Colwyn. 1999. Musicality and the intrinsic motive pulse: Evidence from human psychobiology and infant communication. Musicae Scientiae (Special Issue 1999–2000) 3: 155–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tschacher, Wolfgang, Fabian Ramseyer, and Claudia Bergomi. 2013. The subjective present and its modulation in clinical contexts. Timing & Time Perception 1: 239–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ulbrich, Pamela, Jan Churan, Martina Fink, and Marc Wittmann. 2009. Perception of temporal order: The effects of age, sex, and cognitive factors. Aging, Neuropsychology, and Cognition 16: 183–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Wassenhove, Virginie. 2009. Minding time—An amodel representational space for time perception. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364: 1815–1830.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Wassenhove, Virginie, Ken W. Grant, and David Poeppel. 2007. Temporal window of integration in auditory-visual speech perception. Neuropsychologia 45: 598–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanrullen, Rufin, and Christof Koch. 2003. Is perception discrete or continuous? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7: 207–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, Francisco J. 1999. Present-time consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 6: 111–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vatakis, Argiro, and Charles Spence. 2007. Crossmodal binding: Evaluating the “unity assumption” using audiovisual speech stimuli. Perception & Psychophysics 69: 744–756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wackermann, Jiří. 2007. Inner and outer horizons of time experience. Spanish Journal of Psychology 10: 20–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, Richard M., and Charles J. Obusek. 1972. Identification of temporal order within auditory sequences. Perception & Psychophysics 12: 86–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittmann, Marc. 2014. Embodied time: The experience of time, the body, and the self. In Subjective time: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of temporality, ed. Valtteri Arstila and Dan Lloyd, 507–523. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittmann, Marc, Ernst Pöppel. 2000. Temporal mechanisms of the brain as fundamentals of communication—with special reference to music perception and performance. Musicae Scientiae (Special Issue 1999–2000) 3: 13–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittmann, Marc. 2011. Moments in time. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 5(66).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittmann, Marc, Nicole von Steinbüchel, and Elzbieta Szelag. 2001. Hemispheric specialisation for self-paced motor sequences. Cognitive Brain Research 10: 341–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yarrow, Kielan, Patrick Haggard, Ron Heal, Peter Brown, and John C. Rothwell. 2001. Illusory perceptions of space and time preserve cross-saccadic perceptual continuity. Nature 414: 302–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, Dan. 2005. Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Over the years the empirical and conceptual work presented here was supported by grants from the Bundesministerium für Bildung und Forschung (Berlin), the Max Kade Foundation (New York), the National Institute of Drug Abuse (Bethesda), the Kavli Institute for Brain and Mind (San Diego), the tri-national Neuroscience Network Neurex (Illkirch), and the Fundação Bial (Porto). The author was also supported by the European project COST ISCH Action TD0904 “Time In MEntaL activitY: theoretical, behavioral, bioimaging and clinical perspectives (TIMELY; www.timely-cost.eu).” Thanks go to Bruno Mölder, Valtteri Arstila, and Peter Øhrstrøm for hosting the Turku workshop on “The philosophy and psychology of time: continuity, presence and the timing of experience” (14.8.–15.8.2013). At this meeting I got the chance to exchange with many philosophers and scientists on the topic of temporal presence. From this meeting and from continuous exchange, inspiration came from several people, which I would like to mention, namely Valtteri Arstila, Sean Power, Christoph Hoerl, Oliver Rashbrook, Ian Phillips. Finally, I want to mention the conceptual work on the topic presented here with Carlos Montemayor.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marc Wittmann .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wittmann, M. (2016). The Duration of Presence. In: Mölder, B., Arstila, V., Øhrstrøm, P. (eds) Philosophy and Psychology of Time. Studies in Brain and Mind, vol 9. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-22195-3_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics