Skip to main content

The Power of a Sensitivity Analysis and Its Limit

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Design of Observational Studies

Part of the book series: Springer Series in Statistics ((SSS))

  • 3532 Accesses

Abstract

In an experiment, power and sample size calculations anticipate the outcome of a statistical test that will be performed when the experimental data are available for analysis. In parallel, in an observational study, the power of a sensitivity analysis anticipates the outcome of a sensitivity analysis that will be performed when the observational data are available for analysis. In both cases, it is imagined that the data will be generated by a particular model or distribution, and the outcome of the test or sensitivity analysis is anticipated for data from that model. Calculations of this sort guide many of the decisions made in designing a randomized clinical trial, and similar calculations may usefully guide the design of an observational study. In experiments, the power in large samples is used to judge the relative efficiency of competing statistical procedures. In parallel, the power in large samples of a sensitivity analysis is used to judge the ability of design features, such as those in Chap. 5, to distinguish treatment effects from bias due to unmeasured covariates. As the sample size increases, the limit of the power of a sensitivity analysis is a step function with a single step down from power 1 to power 0, where the step occurs at a value \(\widetilde {\varGamma }\) of Γ called the design sensitivity. The design sensitivity is a basic tool for comparing alternative designs for an observational study.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The omniscient investigator would not test hypotheses. Then again, the omniscient investigator would not run a laboratory or collect data. So, the omniscient investigator would be unable to publish, and would be denied tenure. The omniscient investigator would protest the denial of tenure on the grounds that the university routinely grants tenure to investigators who remain fallible despite their expensive laboratories. The omniscient investigator would end up in an asylum. Be content that you are not an omniscient investigator, and instead try to objectively and publicly control the probability of error.

  2. 2.

    This statement is correct in concept, but it omits a small technical detail. The distribution of Wilcoxon’s statistic, T, is discrete, so its distribution attaches dollops of probability to the possible integer values of T, namely 0, 1, …, \(I\left ( I+1\right ) /2\). In consequence, there may be no value ζ 0.05 such that \(\Pr \left ( \left . T\geq \zeta _{0.05}\right \vert \mathcal {F},\mathcal {Z}\right ) =0.05\). In consequence, the best feasible value, ζ 0.05, is used, that is, the smallest value such that \(\Pr \left ( \left . T\geq \zeta _{0.05}\right \vert \mathcal {F},\mathcal {Z}\right ) \leq 0.05\) when the null hypothesis is true. With this value, ζ 0.05, the probability of rejection of a true hypothesis is less than or equal to 0.05—that is, the test has level 0.05—but the probability of false rejection may be slightly below 0.05—that is, the test has size slightly less than 0.05. In moderately large samples, I, the dollops of probability at integer values of T are very small, so this technical detail may be ignored for conceptual purposes. When an appeal is made to the central limit theorem as I → to justify an approximate Normal null distribution for T, the technical detail disappears.

  3. 3.

    Power will be computed for various continuous distributions of the responses, such as a Normal distribution, and for continuous distributions ties never occur; that is, the probability of a tie is zero. As has been seen several times, ties are a minor inconvenience, easy to address in practice, but they tend to clutter theoretical arguments. As is typically done, ties are assumed absent until a circumstance arises in which it actually becomes important to address the issue.

  4. 4.

    This is expression (4.28) in Lehmann [5, §4.2] except for the exclusion of the continuity correction.

  5. 5.

    The probability \(p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}=\Pr \left ( Y_{i}+Y_{i^{\prime }}>0\right ) \) will turn out to be the most important of the three probabilities. Notice that in (15.6), the quantity \(p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\) dominates the expectation of T, because \(p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\) is multiplied by \(I\left ( I+1\right ) /2\) while p is multiplied by I, so in large samples, as I →, the dominant role is played by \(p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\). Looking back to Sect. 2.5 , we see that \(p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\) is the expectation of \(H_{\mathcal {I}}\) for \(\mathcal {I}=\left \{ i,i^{\prime }\right \} \). As seen in Sect. 2.5 , the quantity \(H_{\mathcal {I}}\) is highly interpretable, and the interpretation carries over to \(p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\).

  6. 6.

    To be precise, we seek the smallest ζ Γ,α such that \( \Pr \left ( \left . T\geq \zeta _{\varGamma ,\alpha }\right \vert \,\mathcal {F}, \mathcal {Z}\right ) \leq \alpha \).

  7. 7.

    See also Note 5 in Sect. 15.1.

Bibliography

  1. Bahadur, R.R.: Rates of convergence of estimates and test statistics. Ann. Math. Stat. 38, 303–24 (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ertefaie, A., Small, D.S., Rosenbaum, P.R.: Quantitative evaluation of the trade-off of strengthened instruments and sample size in observational studies. J. Am. Stat. Assoc. 113, 1122–1134 (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Heller, R., Rosenbaum, P.R., Small, D.: Split samples and design sensitivity in observational studies. J. Am. Stat. Assoc. 104, 1090–1101 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Hodges, J.L., Lehmann, E.L.: Estimates of location based on ranks. Ann. Math. Stat. 34, 598–611 (1963)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Lehmann, E.L.: Nonparametrics. Holden Day, San Francisco (1975). Reprinted: Springer, New York (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Rosenbaum, P.R.: Hodges-Lehmann point estimates of treatment effect in observational studies. J. Am. Stat. Assoc. 88, 1250–1253 (1993)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. Rosenbaum, P.R.: Design sensitivity in observational studies. Biometrika 91, 153–164 (2004)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  8. Rosenbaum, P.R.: Heterogeneity and causality: unit heterogeneity and design sensitivity in observational studies. Am. Stat. 59, 147–152 (2005)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  9. Rosenbaum, P.R.: What aspects of the design of an observational study affect its sensitivity to bias from covariates that were not observed? Festshrift for Paul W. Holland. ETS, Princeton (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Rosenbaum, P.R.: A new U-statistic with superior design sensitivity in matched observational studies. Biometrics 67, 1017–1027 (2011)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  11. Rosenbaum, P.R.: Nonreactive and purely reactive doses in observational studies. In: Berzuini, C., Dawid, A.P., Bernardinelli, L. (eds.) Causality: Statistical Perspectives and Applications, pp. 273–289. Wiley, New York (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  12. Rosenbaum, P.R.: Impact of multiple matched controls on design sensitivity in observational studies. Biometrics 69, 118–127 (2013)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. Rosenbaum, P.R.: Bahadur efficiency of sensitivity analyses in observational studies. J. Am. Stat. Assoc. 110, 205–217 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  14. Rosenbaum, P.R.: Using Scheffé projections for multiple outcomes in an observational study of smoking and periodontal disease. Ann. App. Stat. 10, 1147–1471 (2016)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  15. Small, D., Rosenbaum, P.R.: War and wages: the strength of instrumental variables and their sensitivity to unobserved biases. J. Am. Stat. Assoc. 103, 924–933 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Small, D.S., Cheng, J., Halloran, M.E., Rosenbaum, P.R.: Case definition and design sensitivity. J. Am. Stat. Assoc. 108, 1457–1468 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Werfel, U., Langen, V., Eickhoff, I., Schoonbrood, J., Vahrenholz, C., Brauksiepe, A., Popp, W., Norpoth, K.: Elevated DNA single-strand breakage frequencies in lymphocytes of welders. Carcinogenesis 19, 413–418 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Appendix: Technical Remarks and Proof of Proposition 15.1

Appendix: Technical Remarks and Proof of Proposition 15.1

This appendix contains a proof of Proposition 15.1 in Sect. 15.3. The formula and proof [3, 15] for Wilcoxon’s signed rank statistic are a special case of a general result [7, §3] with the attractive feature that the design sensitivity \( \widetilde {\varGamma }\) has an explicit closed form (15.14).

The approximate power is , where μ F is the expectation of T in the “favorable situation.” An intuitive, heuristic derivation [7, 15] uses the notion that if ζ Γ,α > μ F, then in large samples, as I →, the signed rank statistic T eventually will be less than ζ Γ,α, whereas if ζ Γ,α < μ F, then T will eventually be greater than ζ Γ,α. So the heuristic equates ζ Γ,α in (15.10) and μ F in (15.6) and solves for Γ. It is slightly better to equate ζ Γ,αμ F to 1, let I →, ignore terms that are small compared with I 2, and solve for Γ,

(15.17)
(15.18)

where \(1=\varGamma /\left \{ p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\left ( 1+\varGamma \right ) \right \} \) has solution \(\widetilde {\varGamma }=p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}/\left ( 1-p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\right ) \) as in (15.14). The heuristic is attractive because it uses only the expectation μ F of T in the favorable situation, so the calculation is simple. Alas, the heuristic is “heuristic” precisely because the power depends on \(\left ( \zeta _{\varGamma ,\alpha }-\mu _{F}\right ) /\sigma _{F}\), not on ζ Γ,α − μ F, and the heuristic ignores σ F, hoping that things will work out. Indeed, things do work out, as the proof that follows demonstrates [3]. The general result in [7, §3] shows that the heuristic calculation works quite generally, but the proof that follows is self-contained and does not depend upon the general result.

Proof

For large I, the power, \(\Pr \left ( \left . T\geq \zeta _{\varGamma ,\alpha }\right \vert \,\mathcal {Z}\right ) \), is approximately equal to \(1-\varPhi \left \{ \left ( \zeta _{\varGamma ,\alpha }-\mu _{F}\right ) /\sigma _{F}\right \} \), so the power tends to 1 as I → if \(\left ( \zeta _{\varGamma ,\alpha }-\mu _{F}\right ) /\sigma _{F}\rightarrow -\infty \) and the power tends to 0 as I → if \(\left ( \zeta _{\varGamma ,\alpha }-\mu _{F}\right ) /\sigma _{F}\rightarrow \infty \). Write \(\kappa =\varGamma /\left ( 1+\varGamma \right ) \). Using the expressions for μ F and \( \sigma _{F}^{2}\) from (15.6) and (15.7) in Sect. 15.1 and the expression for ζ Γ,α from (15.10) in Sect. 15.2 yields

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \frac{\zeta _{\varGamma ,\alpha }-\mu _{F}}{\sigma _{F}}=\end{aligned} $$
(15.19)
$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \frac{\kappa I\left( I+1\right) /2+\varPhi ^{-1}\left( 1-\alpha \right) \sqrt{ \kappa \left( 1-\kappa \right) I\left( I+1\right) \left( 2I+1\right) /6} -I\left( I-1\right) p_{1}^{{}^{\prime }}/2-Ip}{\sqrt{I\left( I-1\right) \left( I-2\right) \left( p_{2}^{{}^{\prime }}-\left. p_{1}^{{}^{\prime }}\right. ^{2}\right) +\frac{I\left( I-1\right) }{2}\left\{ 2\left( p-p_{1}^{{}^{\prime }}\right) ^{2}+3p_{1}^{{}^{\prime }}\left( 1-p_{1}^{{}^{\prime }}\right) \right\} +Ip\left( 1-p\right) }}. {} \end{aligned} $$
(15.20)

Expression (15.20) looks untidy at first. Notice, however, that every term in the numerator and denominator of (15.20) involves I, and I →. So divide the numerator and denominator of (15.20) by \(I \sqrt {I}\), and let I →. The last term in the numerator, − Ip, becomes \(-Ip/\left ( I\sqrt {I}\right ) \rightarrow 0\) as I →, whereas the first term in the numerator, \(\kappa I\left ( I+1\right ) /2\), becomes \(\kappa I\left ( I+1\right ) /\left ( 2I\sqrt {I}\right ) \approx \sqrt {I}\kappa /2\) in the sense that their ratio is tending to 1 as I →. Continuing in this way, we find that

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \frac{\zeta _{\varGamma ,\alpha }-\mu _{F}}{\sigma _{F}}\approx \frac{\sqrt{I} \left( \kappa -p_{1}^{{}^{\prime }}\right) }{2\sqrt{p_{2}^{{}^{\prime }}-\left. p_{1}^{{}^{\prime }}\right. ^{2}}}\;\;\mathrm{as}\;\;I\rightarrow \infty \text{ ,} {} \end{aligned} $$
(15.21)

in the sense that the ratio of the left and right sides of (15.21) tends to 1 as I → provided \(\kappa \neq p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\). If \(\kappa >p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\), then (15.21) tends to as I →, so the power tends to 0. If \(\kappa <p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\), then (15.21) tends to − as I →, so the power tends to one. Moreover, \( \kappa =\varGamma /\left ( 1+\varGamma \right ) >p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\) if and only if \( \varGamma >p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}/\left ( 1-p_{1}^{{ }^{\prime }}\right ) \).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

R. Rosenbaum, P. (2020). The Power of a Sensitivity Analysis and Its Limit. In: Design of Observational Studies. Springer Series in Statistics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-46405-9_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics